Preferred Citation: Allen, Michael J. B. Nuptial Arithmetic: Marsilio Ficino's Commentary on the Fatal Number in Book VIII of Plato's Republic. Berkeley:  University of California Press,  c1994 1994. http://ark.cdlib.org/ark:/13030/ft6j49p0qv/


 
PART ONE STUDY


3

PART ONE
STUDY

1
Ficino's Commentary on the Eighth Book of the Republic

"Ultima Cumaei venit iam carminis aetas"


In the notable nineteenth expostulation in his Devotions , John Donne refers to God as a metaphorical God; and the Renaissance in general was enthusiastically attuned to the assumption that the world was itself a figure, a cipher. Necessarily the mathematical structures in the world were part of the divine figuration, and a sense of this figuration provided the foundation for both the methods and the goals of such learned disciplines as arithmology and numerology, astrology, iatromathematics, and musical therapy, the mathematical or at least computational arts that the age regarded as legitimate branches of learning and of proven utility. For the influential book of the Apocrypha known as the Wisdom of Solomon had proclaimed in a much-quoted text that God had made all things "in number, weight, and measure" (11.20[21]) as the architect of the world, as the heavenly geometer, as the musical master of a divine harmonics. And man in the divine image of God the Creator had been designed with a body of geometrical proportions, with a harmoniously balanced temperament, with a mathematical mind. The supreme ancient authority of this mathematical view of man as mathematician was Plato, spokesman for what was preeminently the Pythagorean tradition in which his own scientific studies had been nurtured.

Renaissance scholars were familiar with the report that the inscrip-


4

tion in the vestibule of the Academy had forbidden anyone unskilled in geometry to cross the threshold and seek initiation into the sacred mysteries.[1] For geometry was a marvelous art that the Epinomis 990D had claimed was of divine not human origin, even though, as the Republic had argued at 6.511B ff. and 7.531D–534E, it was subordinate, like all its "sister" mathematical arts, to the "comprehensive" power of dialectic, "the coping stone" of the intellectual skills. Scholars were also aware that in the Timaeus , the dialogue on the Demiurge and his creation and the one most familiar to and most treasured by the medieval and the Renaissance West, Plato had advanced various Pythagorean notions—with what degree of seriousness it is now virtually impossible to say—on the harmonies governing the soul, and on the structure of the elements and the geometrical figures that constituted them.[2] Although none of Plato's dialogues focus primarily on mathematics, several do contain significant loci mathematici . Apart from the Timaeus with its exceptionally important sections on means and proportions at 34B–36D and on the five regular polyhedra at 53C–56C, the Meno has two well-known passages on the duplication of the square at 82B–85B and on the measurement of areas at 86E–87B, the Theaetetus raises the issue of irrational or incommensurable roots at 147D–148B, and the Epinomis (which the Renaissance considered authentic) has an arresting section at 990C–991A on astronomy, geometry, progressions, the mean proportions, and the formation of numbers. Other dialogues contain mathematical references or observations: for instance, the Euthyphro at 12D, the Hippias Major at 303BC, the Philebus at 56D, the Charmides at 166A, the Statesman at 266AB, the Phaedrus at 274C, and the Laws 7 at 817E–820C.[3]

[1] H. D. Saffrey, "Ageômetrêtos mêdeis eisitô: Une inscription légendaire," Revue des études grecques 81 (1968), 67–87, traces the evidence for the inscription (which is possibly apocryphal) back to a reference in an oration by the emperor Julian and to another in a scholion on Aelius Aristides, both from the mid fourth century A.D. ; see also D. H. Fowler, The Mathematics of Plato's Academy: A New Reconstruction (Oxford, 1987), pp. 197–202. The inscription was familiar to Ficino, however, from a number of later sources, including perhaps Philoponus's commentary on Aristotle's De Anima (Ioannis Philoponi in Aristotelis de Anima Libros Commentaria 1.3.406b25 ff., ed. Michael Hayduck, Commentaria in Aristotelem Graeca, vol. 15 [Berlin, 1897], p. 117).

[2] The Timaeus was known to the Latin West principally by way of Calcidius's Commentary. The authoritative modern edition is by J. H. Waszink, Timaeus a Calcidio Translatus Commentarioque Instructus (London and Leiden, 1962; 2d ed., 1975)—volume 4 in the series Corpus Platonicum Medii Aevi ; but see also that by Johannes Wrobel, Platonis Timaeus Interprete Chalcidio cum Eiusdem Commentario (Leipzig, 1876). For Plato's relationship to the Pythagoreans, see Cornelia J. de Vogel, Pythagoras and Early Pythagoreanism (Assen, 1966), pp. 192–207.

[3] For these and other references, see Paul-Henri Michel, De Pythagore à Euclide:

Contribution à l'histoire des mathématiques préeuclidiennes (Paris, 1950), pp. 75–76, 500–511.


5

More generally, the Parmenides is concerned throughout with the metaphysics of the one and the many, of unity and plurality; and the Republic 7.521C–531D outlines a mathematics curriculum in five parts beginning with arithmetic and ratio theory and thence proceeding to plane and solid geometry, and ending with astronomy and music. Finally, there are the complicated metaphysical issues of Plato's postulation, at least according to Aristotle in his Metaphysics 991b9, 1082b23–24, 1086a10–11, and De Anima 404b24, etc., of numbers as Forms, of the mathematicals as intelligible pluralities.

However, the most intractable or mystagogical of all Plato's mathematical speculations (depending on one's point of view) occurs in a passage towards the beginning of the eighth book of the Republic at 546A ff. Here Socrates refers to a mysterious geometric or "fatal" number in order to explain why it is that even perfectly constituted republics—those that do not contain within themselves the seeds of their own decay and ruin—decline nevertheless after the passage of many years into the first of four degenerate forms ending in a tyranny: into a contentious timarchy governed by the passionate pursuit of honor and "a fierce secret longing" for money instead of justice and the good. They are subject, it would seem, to some cyclical cosmic pattern, to an inexorable fate that overwhelms them despite their innate, their Platonic excellence. In the course of this baffling passage on the geometric number Socrates also argues for the necessity of state-planned eugenics. Citizens approaching parenthood must be adjusted to each other, like proportionate numbers, in order that they may breed good, tempered offspring and thus ensure the continuance of balance in the state. And the balance can indeed be maintained for a time: with Platonic planning and Platonic virtue men can work with Fate to ensure the continuance of their state's life or prosperity, as long, that is, as the fatal cycle of years has not yet been fulfilled. After that, no legislation by the magistrates, however wise and however rigorously enforced, can prevail against the inevitable, the periodic change. The eugenic theme is so prominent indeed that Plutarch, Nicomachus of Gerasa, Iamblichus, and Boethius, among others, did not hesitate to identify the fatal geometric number with the notion of a "nuptial" number,[4] presumably because of the sovereign role it plays

[4] Plutarch, De Iside 56 and De Animae Procreatione 10 (Moralia 373F, 1017C); Nicomachus of Gerasa, Introductio 2.24.11; Iamblichus, In Nicomachi Arith. Introd. (ed. Pistelli, 82.20 ff.); and Boethius, De Institutione Arithmetica 2.46 (full citations of

these editions of Nicomachus, Iamblichus, and Boethius are provided below in nn. 74, 76, and 78 respectively).

J. Dupuis, ed. and trans., Théon de Smyrne, philosophe platonicien: Exposition des connaissances mathématiques utiles pour la lecture de Platon (Paris, 1892), p. 388, regards their identification of the nuptial number with the geometric as "impropre," while Auguste Diès, "Le nombre de Platon: Essai d'exégèse et d'histoire," Mémoires présentés par divers savants à l'Académie des inscriptions et belles-lettres (Paris), 14.1 (1940), 9, says that the commentators were correct, "la tradition n'a pas eu tort de lui donner ce nom."


6

in determining, for better or for worse, the fertility of a republic and thus the success of its marriages, begettings, and births.

Of particular importance for Platonic commentators is the fact that Aristotle commented upon this passage adversely in his Politics 5 at 1316a1–b26 in an arresting discussion and dismissal of Socrates' views on the causes of change affecting a perfect commonwealth, such as the hypothetical first state. Aristotle objects that Socrates "treats of revolutions, but not well, for he mentions no cause of change which peculiarly affects the first or perfect state. He only says that the cause is that nothing is abiding, but all things change in a certain cycle; and that the origin of the change consists in those numbers 'of which 4 and 3, married with 5, furnish two harmonies' (he means when the number of this figure becomes solid)."[5] Aristotle is prepared to admit that at times nature may produce bad men who will not submit to education, "in which latter particular he [Socrates] may very likely be not far wrong, for there may well be some men who cannot be educated and made virtuous." Aristotle, who is insisting on the distinction between the "cause" of change and its actual "onset," then raises various objections, among them the following five: Why is "such a cause of change peculiar to his [Socrates'] ideal state, and not rather common to all states, or indeed, to everything which comes into being at all?" Is it merely attributable to the agency of time that "things which did not begin together change together?" Why postulate cyclical change and not merely change, since history furnishes us with many examples of one tyranny passing into another tyranny, not necessarily into another form of government entirely? Isn't it foolish to suppose that a state changes for the worse only because the ruling class begins to acquire

[5] "archên d' einai toutôn, hôn epitritos puthmên pempadi susugeis duo harmonias parechetai, legôn hotan ho tou diagrammatos arithmos toutou genêtai stereos " (1316a4–9). This text has engendered almost as much controversy as Plato's own. Saint Thomas Aquinas himself (or his continuator) complained of its being brief to the point of obscurity (In Arist. Pol. lib. 5, lect. 13). See W. L. Newman, The Politics of Aristotle, 4 vols. (Oxford, 1887–1902), 4:481–482; and Diès, Ess ai , pp. 12 and 60. Cf. nn. 10, 15 below. I am quoting from Benjamin Jowett's translation.


7

too much money? The causes of change are numerous, and yet Socrates mentions only one—the gradual impoverishment of the citizens—as if the citizens had been originally all equally well off. And why speak of revolutions in oligarchies and democracies, as though they each existed in only one form when in fact they exist in many forms?

In short, Aristotle marshals a sequence of powerful objections that charges Socrates with confusing the notion of a temporal cycle with that of temporal change and dismisses his conception of a historical cause as too naive or too simplistic. To anyone who believed in Plato's supremacy over Aristotle, or who was bent upon reconciling the two thinkers, these objections presented a formidable challenge, particularly given Aristotle's belligerent tone, his taking issue with an indisputably major dialogue, and his contentious impatience with the way Socrates had elected to present an important and influential Platonic theme, that of the ideal republic.

The mathematical enigmas in Plato's passage—along with Aristotle's objections—have occasioned speculative debate and intricate analysis since the fifteenth century when they were first rediscovered by the West. A number of "solutions" have been and are still being suggested, and translators have learned to approach Plato's veiled description of the geometric number with some wariness. In the past some have even declined to render it at all. One of the most distinguished of these was Victor Cousin (1792–1867), who footnoted his omission thus: "Ce qui me confond le plus dans cette phrase, d'une obscurité devenue proverbiale, c'est qu'elle n'ait pas plus tourmenté les philosophes grecs, venus après Platon, et qu'ils la citent, la critiquent, la commentent, en n'ayant pas l'air de n'y rien comprendre. . . . [J]e demeure très convaincu qu'une phrase écrite par Platon et commentée par Aristote, est fort intelligible en elle-même."[6] Cousin assumed that an enhanced understanding of ancient mathematics and its terminology would assuredly lead to the untying of what he thought

[6] OEuvres de Platon 10:324, cited by Dupuis, Théon , p. 370. See also Dupuis's earlier study, Le nombre géométrique de Platon (Paris, 1881), pp. 11–12. On p. 8 of the latter Dupuis also adduces the refusal of Humblot, who edited an anonymous translation of the Republic in 1762, to render the mystery of the geometric number. When he came to the famous crux, Humblot substituted the clause, "dont il est inutile de vous expliquer le mystère parce qu'il est au-dessus de votre portée," and footnoted it thus: "Ici est le fameux nombre de Platon, que je n'ai point traduit, parce que je ne l'entends pas; je crois même qu'il est inutile de vouloir se rompre la tête à l'expliquer, personne n'ayant pu le faire avec succés jusqu'à présent."


8

of as "ce noeud embarrassé." The great Friedrich Schleiermacher before him had declared in 1828 that his inability to understand Plato's intentions here and his continually renewed and continually thwarted hopes of doing so had interrupted his work on translating the canon for twelve entire years.[7] Eventually he had reluctantly decided that the value of the geometric number must be 216 (or its square), the product of 8 times 27, the first two "solids" at the two feet of the Platonic lambda as set forth in the Timaeus 35B ff., a text with a special role to play, as we shall see, in the launching of the modern, as well as the ancient, history of the number's interpretation. In our own day another great scholar, Francis M. Cornford, omitted the passage in his 1941 translation of the Republic .

The path of interpretation, moreover, is strewn with failures to calculate the value of this number convincingly for others, though most of these failures are themselves remarkable for their learning and ingenuity. The two preeminent twentieth-century interpreters are James Adam and Auguste Diès;[8] and a shaky consensus arrived at by them and by other scholars has established 12,960,000 as the value that Plato may have had in mind.[9] Even so, discussion continues.[10]

[7] Dupuis, Théon , pp. 369, 394–395; Nombre , pp.10–11; and Diès, Essai , p. 87.

[8] James Adam, The Republic of Plato , 2 vols. (Cambridge, 1902), 2d ed. by D. A. Rees, 2 vols. (Cambridge, 1963), 2:201–209 (commentary), 264–312 (appendix); and Diès, Essai , pp. 5–9. For the preeminence of their solutions, see the note by Desmond Lee (H. D. P. Lee) to his newly revised translation of the Republic , 3d ed. (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1987), pp. 360–361.

[10] For further references to the interpretative history of the geometric number

since the mid nineteenth century, see Adam, Republic , pp. 264–265, and especially Diès, Essai , chapter 4 (chapter 2 deals with the ancient interpretation tradition, and chapter 3 with the period from Faber to Carl Ernst Schneider, i.e., from 1506 to 1833). For more recent views, see Robert S. Brumbaugh, Plato's Mathematical Imagination (Bloomington, Ind., 1954), pp. 107–150; Rees's introduction to Adam, Republic l:xlviii–l; and W. K. C. Guthrie, A History of Greek Philosophy , vol. 4 (Cambridge, 1975), p. 529n.


9

The first modern contributor to the problem of Plato's geometric number, though he has not hitherto received appropriate recognition as we shall see, was Marsilio Ficino (1433–1499), the leading Florentine Neoplatonist of the Renaissance and the architect of Platonism's revival and European dissemination. His most formidable scholarly achievements were undoubtedly his Latin translations of the complete works of both Plato (Florence, 1484; 2d ed., Venice, 1491) and Plotinus (Florence, 1492); and he was recognized in his own age as the supreme interpreter and commentator on Plato. In 1576, nearly eighty years after Ficino's death, Jean Bodin for instance in his Les six livres de la République 4.2 refers to him as "(in mine opinion) the sharpest of all the Academikes."[11] Not surprisingly then, the distinguished Florentine attracted the attention of J. Dupuis in a review of earlier attempts to decipher Plato's enigma that he included in an 1881 monograph, a monograph he subsequently revised and appended to his 1892 edition and French translation of Theon of Smyrna's Expositio .[12]

Following in the footsteps of the great nineteenth-century editor of the Republic , Carl Ernst Christopher Schneider,[13] Dupuis commences his doxology of post-ancient views with Ficino, "le plus ancien interpréte de Platon parmi les modernes." But both merely recall a passing remark in Ficino's argumentum for book 8 as it appeared in his 1484 and 1491 Plato editions—Dupuis uses the 1491—"Quid vero si in eiusmodi verbis plus difficultatis sit quam ponderis"; and this they take

[11] I quote from the lively 1606 translation of Jean Bodin by Richard Knowles, The Six Bookes of a Commonweale , facsimile ed. by Kenneth Douglas McRae (Cambridge, Mass., 1962), p. 458A (misprint for F).

[12] Nombre , pp. 4–16; Théon , pp. 388–399. The monograph itself went through several intermediate revisions—see Dupuis's own bibliographical note, Théon , p. 365n. The 1892 version begins not with Ficino but with Barozzi's 1566 treatise. For Theon's Expositio itself, see pp. 31–33 below.

[13] His edition of the dialogue is entitled, misleadingly, Platonis Opera Graece and consists of 3 vols. in 2 (Leipzig, 1830–1831). In two Commentationes written in 1821 but incorporated into the 1831 praefatio for book 8 of the Republic in the third volume of this edition (i.e., at 3:ii–lxxi), Schneider deals at length with Iacobus Faber Stapulensis (Jacques Lefévre d'Étaples), with Barozzi, and with others, though in an odd order.


10

to mean that for Ficino the passage contained "more of difficulty than of real substance." Schneider assumes that Ficino never followed through on his promise to write more fully on the matter in his Timaeus Commentary; and Dupuis concludes, "il n'indique aucun nombre."[14] Interestingly, this joint dismissal merely echoes a comment made in 1581 by Jean Bodin: "Marsilius Ficinus . . . plainely confesseth himself not to know what Plato in that place ment, fearing lest it should so fall out with him as it did with Iamblichus, who seemeth to have been willing in three words not to have manifested a thing of it selfe most obscure, but rather to have made it darker."[15] Bodin had already followed Ficino in his argumentum in mockingly observing that Aristotle "skippeth over this place as over a dich, neither doth here carpe his maister (as his maner is) when as for the obscuritie thereof he had not wherefore he might reprove him."[16]

Ficino's argumentum , upon which these assumptions of Bodin, of Schneider, and of Dupuis are based, is not without interest. It is one of a number of prefatory argumenta or epitomes that Ficino prepared for each book of the Republic and the Laws and for the other dialogues. They were first published in his 1484 Plato edition and continued to appear in later editions of it and also in the three editions of

[14] Schneider, Platonis Opera Graece 3:iiii; Dupuis, Nombre , p. 5. Dupuis attributes a sentence to Ficino, incidentally, that is not in, and not like anything in, the argumentum !

[15] Again Knowles's translation, p. 458FG. Dupuis, Théon , p. 391, cites the French from Bodin's 1581 version in his Apologie de René Herpin , which was added to the 1583 French edition of Les six livres de la République (first published in 1576), f. 41 verso:

Marsille [sic ] Ficin, le plus grand Platonicien qui ait escrit, confesse qu'il ny entend rien, et non sans cause Ciceron disoit qu'il n'y avoit rien plus difficile que les nombres de Platon. Et Theon Smyrnean, des plus illustres Mathematiciens entre les Academiques, interpretant la Republique de Platon, n'a aucunement touché ce passage. Procle Academicien, ayant doctement interpreté les sept premiers livres de la Republique de Platon, est demeuré a l'huictiesme, où il est question de ces nombres. Et quoy que Jamblique se soit efforcé d'esclaircir ce passage, si est ce qu'il a encores plus obscurcy.

See also Schneider, Platonis Opera Graece 3:liii. In actuality, Bodin was merely following Ficino's review of the ancient authorities in his argumentum .

In his expanded Latin version of 1586 Bodin presents a lengthy exposition of Plato's passage in which, according to Diès, Essai , pp. 59 ff., he attacks the interpretation of Faber Stapulensis without naming him (see n. 34 below). Bodin himself proposed no solution on the grounds that Plato's presentation of it made no sense and that he must have been distracted at the time—"ut planum sit Platonem eo loco sui ipsius oblitum esse" (De Republica Libri Sex Latine ab Autore Redditi [Lyons and Paris, 1586], p. 417)! See Schneider, Platonis Opera Graece 3:xxxxviiii–lviii, and Diès, Essai , p. 56.

[16] Trans. Knowles, p. 457E ("Primus quidem Aristoteles locum hunc quasi vallum transiit, neque, ut solet, magistrum momordit, cum propter obscuritatem non haberet

que parte illum carperet," De Republica Libri Sex , p. 412). See Schneider, Platonis Opera Graece 3:liii; Dupuis, Nombre , p. 7; Diès, Essai , p. 13.


11

Ficino's own Opera Omnia (where the argumentum for the eighth book appears on p. 1413). Professor Paul Oskar Kristeller has argued convincingly that each argumentum was composed as Ficino completed his translation of the dialogue it was to preface, though the argumenta as a body were probably revised later and further crossreferences added.[17] If he is correct, then the argumentum for the eighth book would date from the late 1460s, since the book itself is number 38 in the sequence of the dialogues as he translated them (counting each book of the Republic separately) and a draft of the sequence was completed during the rule of Piero, Cosimo de' Medici's son and successor, who did not die until 1469.[18]

In the argumentum Ficino observes that it was not unjustly that Cicero had written that Plato's fatal number had become proverbial for obscurity—a reference to the Epistle to Atticus 7.13.5—and that Theon of Smyrna, otherwise the principal expounder of Platonic mathematics, had very astutely decided to omit all consideration of the number in his Expositio on the grounds that Plato's mystery was "inexplicable."

As the champion of Plato, Ficino has as his immediate goal, however, to refute Aristotle's objections to—what he characterizes as "calumnies" against—the views of Socrates concerning the cause of a perfectly constituted state's ultimate decline, the state that Ficino interprets Socrates as having already fully described in the first seven books of the Republic . Since this is one of the most prominent instances of disagreement between Plato and Aristotle, it naturally forced itself upon Ficino's attention.[19]

[17] Supplementum Ficinianum , 2 vols. (Florence, 1937; reprint 1973), 1:cxvi–cxvii, cxlvii if.; see also his "Marsilio Ficino as a Beginning Student of Plato," Scriptorium 20 (1966), 41–54 at 46 ff., in answer to the arguments of Raymond Marcel in Marsile Ficin (1433–1499) (Paris, 1958), pp. 457–458, that Ficino only wrote the argumenta in 1475–1476 after he had finished translating all the dialogues. Marcel was reviving a hypothesis first put forward by Arnaldo della Torre in Storia dell' Accademia Platonica di Firenze (Florence, 1902), pp. 606–607. See also James Hankins, Plato in the Italian Renaissance , 2 vols. (Leiden, 1990), 1:318–321, 2:483–485.

[18] Kristeller, Supplementum 1:cil.

[19] For Ficino the most accessible and authoritative Latin translation of Aristotle's Politics , and the only Quattrocento one, was by Leonardo Bruni, who composed it between 1435 and 1437 (it was published in 1469); see Hans Baron, ed., Leonardo Bruni Aretino: Humanistisch-philosophische Schriften (Leipzig and Berlin, 1928), pp. 143, 175–176; Eugenio Garin, "Le traduzioni umanistiche di Aristotele nel secolo XV," Atti

e memorie dell' Accademia fiorentina di scienze morali "La Columbaria" 16 (1951), 55–104 at 67–68; and Gordon Griffiths in The Humanism of Leonardo Bruni: Selected Texts , translations with introductions, by Gordon Griffiths, James Hankins, and David Thompson (Binghamton, N.Y., 1987), pp. 113–115, also pp. 38, 109, 154–170. A glance at the relevant passage, however, clearly demonstrates that Ficino did not turn to Bruni, at least in this instance:

Inquit enim causam esse mutationis, quia sic natura comparatum sit ut nihil permaneat, sed in ambitu quodam temporis mutationem recipiat. Esse vero principium horum inquit quorum sexquitertium fundum quinario coniugatum duas exhibet harmonias, inquiens, quando numerus diagrammatis huiusmodi efficiatur solidus, utputa natura producente pravos, & meliores disciplina. Hoc ergo forsan inquit non male. (Cited from the 1542 Venice edition of Bruni's translation, f. 139v.)

Similarly, Ficino did not use the standard medieval translation of the Politics by William of Moerbeke (c. 1215–1286), which dates from around 1260 and was made perhaps at the request of Aquinas. See M. Grabmann, Guglielmo di Moerbeke (Rome,

1946, pp. 111–113; and Bernard G. Dod's chapter "Aristoteles Latinus" in The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy , ed. Norman Kretzmann, Anthony Kenny, and Jan Pinborg, with Eleonore Stump (Cambridge, 1982), pp. 45–79 at 49–50, 62–64, and 78. This version is preserved in some 107 MSS and was edited by F. Susemihl in 1872 for the Teubner series as Aristotelis Politicorum Libri Octo, cum Vetusta Translatione Guilelmi de Moerbeka . The relevant passage reads:

ait enim caussam [sic ] esse id, quod est non manere aliquid, sed in aliqua periodo transmutari, principium autem esse horum, quorum epitritus fundus quinario coniugatus duas harmonias exhibet, dicens, quando numerus diagrammatis huius solidus fuerit, tamquam natura quandoque producente pravos et meliores disciplina, hoc ipsum dicens forte non male. (Pp. 590.9–591.3)

Given Ficino's fierce scrutiny of the passage, we must conclude, therefore, that he probably turned to the Greek text of Aristotle directly and made his own translation from one of the many manuscripts of the work available to him (the first complete edition of the Greek Aristotle was about to issue in five volumes from the Aldine press in 1495–1498, but obviously too late for him to use here)

We might note incidentally that he may have dipped into Donato Acciaiuoli's commentary on the passage, a commentary written in the early 1470s and based on the lectures of Argyropoulos. Acciaiuoli quotes Bruni's Latin version as cited above (I have consulted the Venice 1566 edition Donati Acciaioli in Aristotelis Libros Octo Politicorum Commentarii , fol. 194r-v) and then argues that Aristotle is postulating a cube number resulting "ex sexquitertio et quinario"—which he identifies as nine, the origin of the Platonic great year!—and also that "diagrammatis" means "descriptionis." Still, his analysis is very brief and nothing suggests that Ficino would have found anything particularly useful or illuminating in it. See Hankins, Plato in the Italian Renaissance 1:124; and Arthur Field, The Origins of the Platonic Academy in Florence (Princeton, 1988), pp. 204, 226–229.


12

He counters the Stagirite's arguments by postulating two kinds of causes of change. The first is specific in that it occasions "the permutations alike of souls and of states from one form to another," the changes particular to an imperfect soul or state. But a perfect soul or state, such as that postulated here by Socrates, cannot be supposed to contain this kind of cause on the Platonic grounds that that which is perfect cannot degenerate. The second kind is a "common" or universal cause of change and it is to be identified, if not with Fate itself, then certainly with the "fatal order" that governs the temporal realm. For change in this realm is brought about by the shifting configurations, the "fatal order" of the celestial spheres and the planetary conjunctions and oppositions. Against the great cycles of Fate and its instrument, the stars, no sublunar form, perfect or imperfect, is immune. While men and states may possess the internal fortitude and virtue to endure for the full duration of their destined, their fatal time on earth, they must succumb eventually to change, not necessarily because of any innate defect—though most sublunar entities have such defects—but because of the universal condition of mutability. Interestingly, Ficino, the son of a physician and himself trained initially as a physician, suggests that we might think of the contrast as that between an endemic and an epidemic disease. Thus Ficino distinguishes between the minor "revolutions" that concern Aristotle and the great cycles of time that concern Plato.

The greatest astronomical cycle is the Platonic "great year," which is defined in the Timaeus 39D as the time it takes for the seven planetary spheres and the sphere of the fixed stars to return to the positions they had occupied at the beginning of the cycle—a "Pythagorean"


13

conception that can be traced back at least to Oenopides of Chios (fl. c. 450–425 B.C. ).[20] The Platonists (and Stoics) entertained the corollary speculation that mankind too is governed by its own great year, which they identified as the time when history comes full circle and begins to repeat itself. The obvious question arises whether the two great years—that of the celestial spheres and that of mankind—are coterminous. Plutarch, for instance, had argued that they were in his essay De Fato 3 (Moralia 569A-C). When the heavens are restored to the state they were in at the beginning of the great year, then everything on earth including man will return to its first condition and history begin again; fate is thus both finite and infinite.[21] But others had

[20] Cf. Timaeus 39D: "the perfect number of time fulfills the perfect year when all the eight revolutions, having their relative degrees of swiftness, are accomplished together and attain their completion at the same time." See Dupuis, Théon , p. 366, citing Theon's Expositio 3.40 (ed. Hiller, p. 198.14 ff.), for which see n. 67 below.

[21] Cf. Calcidius, In Timaeum 148 (ed. Wrobel, p. 206.12–24); see also Dupuis, Théon , pp. 366–367. Apokatastasis , in the sense of the return of the cosmos to its former state—apokatastaseis appears as a bad variant, we might note, for apostaseis in the Republic 8.546B6—is a term of some importance in the Corpus Hermeticum ,

in various Stoic and Neoplatonic treatises, and, given the reference in Acts 3:21, in Christian eschatological commentary, above all in Origen.


14

contended that the one great year was a multiple of the other. Proclus, for instance, had held that the great year of mankind was a multiple of the cosmic great year, whereas others had argued precisely the opposite.[22] Moreover, the value of the cosmic great year was variously reckoned. Macrobius, for instance, had calculated it as 15,000 ordinary years,[23] while the Neoplatonic and Ptolemaic traditions to which Ficino is here subscribing had determined upon 36,000 years.[24]

In the Republic Plato does not actually say, however, that the period of the cosmic great year is measured by the perfect number or numbers, but declares rather at 546B3–4 that the perfect number presides over the period of "divine begettings." And though Theon of Smyrna for one had assumed that the cosmic great year was governed by a perfect number—in this case six, the first of such numbers—and was therefore indeed a "divine begetting,"[25] nonetheless we must dis-

[22] Dupuis, Théon , p. 371, cites a passage from Proclus's In Timaeum book 4 (p. 271 in the Basel ed. of 1534). This is to be found in the standard ed. by Ernst Diehl, Procli Diadochi in Platonis Timaeum Commentaria , 3 vols. (Leipzig, 1903–1906), at 3:93.18–94.4, and in the trans. by André-Jean Festugière, Proclus: Commentaire sur le Timée , 5 vols. (Paris, 1966–1969), at 4:122—Proclus alludes, interestingly, to the Platonic Number at 93.23–25. However, Ficino almost certainly did not know Proclus's fourth book, since his exemplar, the Riccardiana's gr. 24, ends in the middle of the third book at the word sômasi (ed. Diehl, 2:169.4; cf. l:xi ff.).

[23] In Somnium Scipionis 2.11.8–13. Cf. Cicero, De Natura Deorum 2.20.51–53—but Cicero does not mention the fixed stars.

[24] See, for instance, Ficino's argumenta for Republic 10 and Laws 6 (Opera Omnia , 2d ed. [Basel, 1576], pp. 1431, 1505): "When he says the twelve parts of the city follow the circuit of the universe, perhaps too he means that the whole circuit of the eighth sphere is perfected in 36,000 years, which number indeed is perfectly completed by having three [periods] of twelve thousand years to the extent that in the first twelve thousand years you may understand from the opinion of the ancients the youthful habit of the whole world, in the second twelve the mature (virilem ) habit, in the third twelve the senile habit. But concerning these matters more opportunely in the Timaeus " (1505). In summa 20 of the Timaeus Commentary (Opera , p. 1468.2) he declares, however, that many think of this great year—"which is completed from the flood when all the circuits of the stars are complete around the world's center and their own center and all the stars together are brought back equally to the same part of the celestial longitude, latitude and height as they originally occupied"—as fifteen solar years, "while others measure it otherwise." This is presumably a reference to Macrobius. See Chapter 4 below.

For the associations of 36 as the sum of the first four even and the first four odd numbers, as the first number which is at once square and triangular, and as the number which is both the product of two squares (4×9) and the sum of three cubes (1+8+27), see Plutarch, De Animae Procreatione 13, 30 (Moralia 1018CD, 1027F).

[25] See Dupuis, Théon , pp. 376–377 and n. with references. For Ficino and the perfect numbers see Chapter 2 below.


15

tinguish in our own minds, at least initially, between the notions of the cosmic great year, of the perfect number(s), and of the fatal number(s), remembering that the Platonic number, which presides over "mortal" begettings, is a fatal number.

Ficino's position is this. The period of the great year necessarily contains lesser periods, and these are the periods of human engendering which are under the sway of the fatal geometric number. However, this number is itself subordinate to the perfect number that governs the divine cosmic creature which is the world (the "divine begetting"). The perfect number, not the fatal number, therefore is the ultimate determinant of celestial time, the world's time that is intermediary between terrestrial time and timeless eternity. But such a number eludes human intelligence, says Ficino, and is known to the gods, to God alone, for whom a thousand years, in the words of Psalm 90:4, are but as yesterday when it is past. If the Psalmist is to be believed, however, there emerges the possibility at least of an analogical relationship between God's measures and man's, and thus of our predicating on the basis of our circumscribed notion of a period (and thence of periodicity) the existence of divinely ordered periods that God has ordained should govern the world until the dawning of the great Sabaoth of His eternity.

However speculatively appealing, the task of actually measuring periodic time and its constitutive units, and therefore of establishing the basis for prediction itself, is utterly beyond man's reasoning powers. In the first place, the reason has no way of determining our position in a period (which may be part of a greater and even more mysterious period or cycle, and so on), and hence of determining when it began and when it will end. Thus it cannot know the number that governs our present period as its originating and therefore as its final cause. Yet such a cause, such a universal cause, and not particular and local causes, is precisely what Plato is concerned with. Accordingly, Plato does not resort, Ficino argues in this argumentum , to "the civil faculty" of the reason, like his calumniator, Aristotle, in order to measure the ultimate life of a state. Rather he has recourse to the faculty that transcends man's reason, to the suprarational, intuitive understanding (the mens ) that, insofar as it is concerned with the apprehension of time, is identical with "Apollo's prophetic art," or what Ficino refers to also as the "oracular" power bestowed on us by the Muses.[26]

[26] "Quoniam vero eiusmodi causae assignatio praesentis civilisque facultatis terminos procul excedit, ideo Socrates vaticinio Musarum utitur, et profecto ita utitur ut et

nobis ad haec interpretanda opus sit Apollinis vaticinio"; noted by Schneider, Platonis Opera Graece 3:iv.


16

Ficino's account of prophecy has never been fully analyzed, nor for that matter has his conception of Apollo or the Muses; and it is part of his general theory, derived principally from the Phaedrus 244A–245C, of the four divine furies. We learn from an important section in his Platonic Theology 13.2 (completed, at least in draft, by 1474 but not published until 1482) that he viewed prophecy as culminating in the soul's ascension from the body and "comprehension of all place and time." At that moment the intuitive intellect is flooded with the splendor of the Ideas, the radiant Beauty that is the emanating light of Truth.[27] But the prophetic "art" involves more than the initiatory rapture and then the intellectual skill and insight to interpret it correctly. In the argumentum , Ficino claims, perhaps extravagantly or facetiously, that the mysteries of the passage on the fatal geometric number and the mystery of that number itself not only defy interpretation by the process of normal discursive reasoning (the ratio ) and require intuitive or even mantic powers, but demand ultimately the descent of a god, of a divine and overwhelming force. Perhaps we should bear in mind a claim that Ficino had made elsewhere, namely that mathematics is the particular domain of the daemons and that skill with numbers is in essence a daemonic skill and the gift of the daemons,[28] something that most of us have suspected since childhood.

Even so, the argumentum strikes a note of doubt. In the light of Theon of Smyrna's refusal to address the great mystery, despite his expertise in Platonic mathematics, Ficino wonders, as we have seen, whether there is "more of difficulty than of real weight" in Plato's reference to the fatal geometric number, especially given the reference at 545DE to the stupefying effect of the Muses' "tragically inflated" mode on a simple youthful soul. At this point he declines, furthermore, to address the technical difficulties of the passage or indeed to confront the mystery itself of the fatal number; and he suggests in-

[27] Ed. and trans. Raymond Marcel, as Marsile Ficin: Théologie platonicienne de l'immortalité des âmes , 3 vols. (Paris, 1964–1970), 2:205–214. On inspiration in Ficino, see my Platonism , chapter 1, and Sebastiano Gentile, "In margine all 'Epistola 'De divino furore' di Marsilio Ficino," Rinascimento , 2d ser., 23 (1983), 33–77.

[28] In the Platonic Theology 14.3 (ed. Marcel, 2:256) Ficino argues that "we live the life of the daemons when we engage in mathematical speculation," and contemplate cogitabilia , that is, mathematical matters. Cf. his epitome for Proclus's Republic Commentary 12, "Cogitabilia vero, id est mathematica, res in se quaedam speciesque sunt" (Opera , p. 942.1). In the Platonic Theology 6.2 (ed. Marcel, 1:228), he declares that numbers are spiritual entities or forms (spirituales ).


17

stead that the reader should turn to his Timaeus Commentary—his earliest commentary, we recall—for whatever is "more useful or opportune" in Plato's baffling discussion, though we should note that in that commentary Ficino does not take up the issue of the fatal number, despite his odd references to the pertinent passage in the Republic .[29] The remaining sentences of the argumentum merely cull some "moral precepts" from the rest of book 8.

Clearly, at this stage in his Platonic career Ficino did not have the confidence to expatiate on an issue he had not yet resolved; indeed he was probably ambivalent, on the one hand suspecting that Plato was playing or joking with his reader, on the other believing that a divine inspiration was required for an interpreter to pierce through the cloudy veils with which Plato had encompassed the number to conceal it from the vulgar gaze.[30] In either event, it was clear that Plato had hedged the passage around with apotropaic devices, with Pythagorean prohibitions, with learned silence. And not only to the young and uninitiated, and to those with the mere rudiments of geometry had he denied its resolution: Ficino himself felt compelled to wait upon some future inspiration, some descent of Apollo or his daemon.[31] Having

[29] For the possible references, see the Index Auctorum et Nominum, below.

[30] Ficino seems, for instance, to have thought of Plato's concentration in books 8, 9, and 10 of the Republic on numbers ending in 8, 9, and zero respectively as an example both of veiling and of playing. He was fully apprised, nevertheless, of Plato's own reservations in the Protagoras 342 ff. and the Cratylus passim about the symbolic use of number, and of Plato's mercurial way with images and figures. See his references in the De Numero Fatali 15 to Plato's deployment of numerical metaphors in the Phaedrus . More generally, see his remarks in the Phaedrus Commentary, summa 25 (ed. M. J. B. Allen, Marsilio Ficino and the Phaedran Charioteer [Berkeley, Los Angeles, London, 1981], pp. 168–171), written just a few months before, and his contention in the dedicatory proem to his Plato edition that "Platonic jokes and games are much more serious than the serious discourse of the Stoics" ( = Opera , p. 1129). On Ficino and the varying semantic levels in Plato, see Hankins, Plato in the Italian Renaissance , 1:337–339, 344.

We might note that Ficino also thought of Plotinus as playing, and playing specifically "in the Egyptian manner," with regard to the theme of the possibility of the human soul's transmigration into the soul or the body of a beast: Opera , p. 1788.5 (the commentary on Enneads 6.7.6).

[31] The apollonian daemon is referred to in Ficino's Phaedrus Commentary, summae 10 and 30 (ed. Allen, pp. 139, 183). Given the reference in the Apology 23B to Apollo being Socrates' own god, it is associated with Socrates's warning voice and thus with his personal daemon. See my The Platonism of Marsilio Ficino (Berkeley, Los Angeles, London, 1984), pp. 21–22, 31, 33, 66–67.

In his Vita Platonis Ficino repeats the story that Plato was a son of Apollo. This Vita , which is deeply indebted to Diogenes Laertius's life of Plato in his Lives of the Philosophers , appeared as a preface for Ficino's 1484 Plato edition (succeeding the dedicatory proem to Lorenzo) and again as a letter addressed to Francesco Bandini in the

fourth book of Ficino's Epistulae (Opera , pp. 763–770; trans. in Letters [see n. 41 below], 3:32–48—the reference occurs at p. 770.3).


18

said this, we should note that Ficino did accept the scholarly responsibility of attempting a translation of the passage; and in doing so he relied upon his exemplar, the Laurenziana's 85.9.[32]

However, the story of Ficino's involvement did not end here, as Bodin, Schneider, Dupuis, and others have too precipitately supposed.

Apparently, these scholars were familiar only with Ficino's argumentum , which offers no solution to the problem of the geometric number. They were obviously completely unaware, as all more recent

[32] This codex contains the complete works of Plato in a good text in the A family and with abundant marginalia by Ficino. See Sebastiano Gentile in Marsilio Ficino e il ritorno di Platone: Mostra di manoscritti, stampe e documenti (17 maggio—6 giugno 1984) , ed. Sebastiano Gentile, Sandra Niccoli, and Paolo Viti (Florence, 1984), pp. 28–31 (no. 22) and plate VII—hereafter Mostra —with further references to earlier studies by Marcel, Sicherl, Kristeller et al.; idem, "Note sui manoscritti greci di Platone utilizzati da Marsilio Ficino," in Scritti in onore di Eugenio Garin (Pisa, 1987), pp. 51–84 at 58. See also Aubrey Diller, "Notes on the History of Some Manuscripts of Plato," in his Studies in Greek Manuscript Tradition (Amsterdam, 1983), pp. 251–258 at 257; Paul Oskar Kristeller, Marsilio Ficino and His Work after Five Hundred Years , Quaderni di Rinascimento, no. 7 (Florence, 1987), pp. 72–74, 138; Gerard Boter, The Textual Tradition of Plato's Republic (Leiden, 1989), pp. xvii (the stemma where MS. 85.9 is assigned the siglum c ), 36–37 (its description), 137–139 (its relationship to MS. 59.1, which is assigned the siglum a ), and 270–278 (Ficino's use of it as his primary but not exclusive source); and James Hankins, "Cosimo de' Medici and the 'Platonic Academy,'" Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes 53 (1990), 144–162 at 157–158.

Diller and Gentile have both conjectured that Cosimo acquired the codex in 1438 during the Ferrara-Florence Council of Union not from the emperor but from one of the most distinguished members of his suite, the philosopher Gemistus Pletho. Its scribe has been tentatively identified by N. G. Wilson as Christophorus de Persona, who ended his career as papal librarian to Innocent VIII but who had probably studied under Pletho in his youth (see Hankins, "Cosimo," pp. 157–159, with further references).

Cosimo gave Ficino the codex to use in 1462. It contained, besides the complete canon of Plato (the Republic being on fols. 216–267), a number of other texts of great interest to him: the Definitiones and other Platonic spuria, the Golden Verses of Pythagoras, Alcinous's Epitome , Theon of Smyrna's Expositio , the "Life of Plato" by Diogenes Laertius, Albinus's Introductio , the De Anima Mundi by Timaeus Locrus, the De Animae Procreatione by Plutarch, and the Economics and Symposium by Xenophon; it also contained an oration by Aristides and another by Libanius. With regard to the Plato, scholarly opinion now holds that it was probably copied directly from the Laurenziana's 59.1 earlier in the fifteenth century—probably in Crete. For MS. 59.1 itself did not appear in Lorenzo's collection until it was brought to Florence by Janus Lascaris, who had bought it for him in Candia on 3 April 1492. It is extremely unlikely, therefore, as Diller and Gentile have recently argued (and Kristeller now agrees), that Ficino ever consulted MS. 59.1 for his Plato translations.

We should note that Boter is obviously unfamiliar with this newly skeptical view of MS. 59.1's importance for Ficino and therefore unwilling to dismiss it as one of Ficino's exemplars for the Republic translation. He also maintains that Ficino made occasional use of several other manuscripts, including one of Bessarion's (now the Marciana's gr. 187 [coll. 742]), and the Laurenziana's 85.7 (a member of the F family). Again, however, recent scholarship on Ficino has discounted MS. 85.7 as a likely source (see Kristeller, Ficino and His Work , pp. 74, 138); and the question of Ficino's access to the Marciana's MS has not been seriously raised before, but is of little bearing since that MS was itself copied from the Laurenziana's 85.9 (see L. A. Post, The Vatican Plato and Its Relations [Middletown, Conn., 1934], pp. 40 ff., and Boter's own p. 59). Interestingly, however, Gentile, "Note," pp. 69 ff., has proved that Ficino did collate MS. 85.9 with two MSS containing single dialogues or excerpts, the Laurenziana's Conventi soppr. 180 and the Vatican's Borgianus gr. 22; but neither includes the Republic .

Note that Dupuis's claim, Nombre , p. 9, that Ficino adopted the variants treis apokatastaseis for treis apostaseis, parechêtai for parechetai , and pempadôn for pempado is incorrect; he was almost certainly thinking of Barozzi's readings (see n. 35 below).

Finally, with regard to the question of Ficino's indebtedness to the three humanist Latin renderings that preceded his own, see Appendix 2 below.


19

scholars too have been unaware, of a major essay on the theme and its implications that Marsilio wrote some thirty years later in the early 1490s and published in 1496. There he takes up several of the many problems in some detail, and having insisted on the role of the diagonal numbers (diametri or diametrales ) as we shall see, he advances a solution consonant with Aristotle's gloss, namely, 12 to the third power. This solution apparently became generally accepted during the first half at least of the sixteenth century. It was adopted, for instance, by Raphael (Maffei) Volaterranus in the 35th book of his Commentaria urbana published in Rome in 1506 (though he proferred another solution in his 36th book!),[33] and adopted too, more significantly, by Iacobus Faber Stapulensis (Jacques Lefèvre d'Étaples), again in 1506, in annotations to the last chapter of his commentary on book 5 of Aristotle's Politics, a commentary that was reprinted a number of times and exerted considerable influence in its day.[34] It was also adopted, but with more detailed argumentation and annotation and

[33] Schneider, Platonis Opera Graece 3:lxix, Dupuis, Nombre , p. 6, Diès, Essai , pp. 73–74 (with errors).

[34] For the various editions, see the bibliography by Eugene F. Rice, Jr. in his edition, The Prefatory Epistles of Jacques Lefèvre d'Étaples and Related Texts (New York and London, 1972), pp. 553–554 (with the relevant preface on pp. 150–152). Faber's annotations amount to four pages; for an analysis, see Schneider, Platonis Opera Graece 3:lviiii–lxviii; and Diès, Essai , pp. 59–71. Diès claimed, given the absence for so long of Proclus's interpretation, that it was Faber who had first brought to bear the theory of the diagonal and the lateral numbers, an essential source for the modern solution of the Platonic enigma (pp. 66, 69). But credit for this must go to Ficino, or at least to Ficino's promotion of Theon's Expositio ; see his De Numero Fatali 5, and Chapter 2 below.

Interestingly, in the course of his argument Faber quotes verbatim from Ficino's translation of Plato's passage, but only as it appears at the head of the 1496 essay and not in the 1484 or 1491 Platonis Opera Omnia editions; for Faber's version includes the 1496 emendations, including the major emendation "quinitatis . . . comparabiles." This is irrefutable evidence in itself that he knew of Ficino's essay (though Diès, Essai , p. 61, incorrectly supposed that the translation was Faber's own). In 1496 Faber published an edition of the Arithmetica of Jordanus Nemorarius (d. 1237), along with an epitome of the arithmetical works of Boethius—a significant volume for Renaissance mathematics—and in 1503 another epitome of the arithmetical works of Boethius and of others, along with an introduction. In neither, however, does he deal with Plato's number.


20

again with an insistence on the bearing of the diagonal numbers, by the distinguished Venetian mathematician Francesco Barozzi in his Commentarius in Locum Platonis Obscurissimum published in Bologna in 1566.[35]

The history, rich and curious in itself, of interpretative attempts before the twentieth century should therefore be rewritten to accord Ficino, and not Faber, the accolade of being the architect of the first modern interpretation of Plato's enigma and the first scholar since antiquity to confront a number of the major cruces and to address the issues and possibilities in the light of research into Platonic mathematics.[36] We might note, incidentally, that Girolamo Cardano (1501–

[35] Dupuis, Théon , p. 389: "La dissertation de Barozzi est une des plus soignées. La version latine littérale du lieu est une des meilleures"; also Nombre , pp. 6 (though with incorrect dates for the 1566 edition and for Barozzi's death in 1604) and 20–47 passim. Barozzi's translation is to be found on fol. 12r, lines 13–28, and his solution on fol. 17v, line 32. For an analysis, see Schneider, Platonis Opera Graece 3:iiii–xxviiii, and Diès, Essai , pp. 69–85, who supposes that Barozzi's immediate debt was to Faber (for whom see pp. 66–67). We might note that Barozzi's Latin rendering is almost Ficino's revised version of 1496 (perhaps because Barozzi had his eye on Faber—see n. 34 above). His principal variants are "(in)effabilia," "quinarius," and "praelongiori" for Ficino's "(in)comparabilia," "quinitas," and "oblongiori(e)" respectively. Since Jean Bodin knew only Ficino's 1484 argumentum , we must suppose that he too was unaware of Faber's debt to Ficino's later essay.

[36] The opening of the third chapter of Diès's monograph in particular should be revised, since it is, and is likely to remain, the authoritative history of the attempts to interpret Plato's Number up to 1940. More research still remains to be done, however, on a variety of sixteenth- and seventeenth-century editions of, and commentaries on, the Republic . The following possibilities have been suggested to me by Professor James Hankins: Joachim Camerarius the Elder, Epistularum Familiarium Libri VI (Frankfurt, 1583), pp. 255 ff., 478–481, 525; Ulysse Aldrovandi, Bologna Univ., Aldrovandi MS. 124, vol. 56, fols. 270–277; Sebastian Fox Morzillus, Commentatio in X Platonis Libros de Republica (Basel, 1556); Muretus, Commentarium in Rempublicam , Vat. lat. 11591—published, misleadingly, in his Commentarii in Aristotelis X Libros Ethicorum ad Nicomachum (Ingolstadt, 1602), 712–740; Joh. Sleidanus, Summa Doctrinae Platonis de Republica et de Legibus , in Cl. Seyssel, De Republica Galliae et Regum Officiis (Strasbourg, 1548); and Ioannes Sozomenus, Divi Platonis de Republica Libri X (Venice, 1626).


21

1576), in his Opus Novum de Proportionibus (Basel, 1570), was to propose as a solution another number occurring in Ficino's analysis, 8128, the fourth in the series of perfect numbers; and that the disciple and friend of Descartes, Marin Mersenne (1588–1648), in book 2 of his Traité de l'harmonie universelle (Paris, 1627), was to propose a "lesser fatal number" that Ficino had actually entertained—since Plato himself had introduced it in the ninth book of the Republic —namely 729;[37] and so forth. Clearly, early modern scholarship had not yet forgotten Ficino's role in the explication of Plato's refractory passage.

Ficino's essay takes the form of a commentary on book 8 of the Republic , which he first published along with others in 1496 (no earlier manuscript is extant). It therefore postdates the Plato editions of 1484 and 1491 and represents a renewed attempt by Ficino late in his life to come to grips with the value of Plato's geometric number. From the onset of his professional academic career he had committed himself to the task of extensive commentary on the Platonic dialogues. Even before he had learned Greek in the 1450s, he had written at length on the Timaeus , though he was to do so again on several other occasions—the Timaeus Commentary we now possess being the product of maturer explication.[38] By 1469 he had already completed a fullscale commentary on the Symposium and written a substantial portion of another one on the Philebus (though this he never completed despite returning to it on at least two more occasions).[39] In the following years, as he prepared his Plato translation for the press, he finished composing his epitomes and introductions for all the dialogues.[40]

[37] Cardanus, De Proportionibus , p. 234, prop. CCV "super verbis Platinis de fine Reipub." (in the 1663 Lyons ten-volume edition of Cardano's collected works this occurs at 4:582); and Mersenne (pseudonym "le sieur de Sermes"), Traité , book 2, theorem XIII, part 1, pp. 424–436 at 430 (there is an acknowledgment, incidentally, to Ficino, Cardano, and Faber on p. 426). See Dupuis, Nombre , pp. 6–8; idem, Théon , pp. 392–393; Diès, Essai , pp. 85–86; and, for Cardanus, Schneider, Platonis Opera Graece 3:xxxviii–xxxx. Dupuis and Diès are incorrect in citing Cardanus's propositio as CCXV.

[38] For the history of the Timaeus Commentary, see Kristeller, Supplementum 1:cxxi, 78–79, and my "Marsilio Ficino's Interpretation of Plato's Timaeus and Its Myth of the Demiurge," in Supplementum Festivum: Studies in Honor of Paul Oskar Kristeller , ed. James Hankins, Frederick Purnell Jr., and John Monfasani (Binghamton, N.Y., 1987), pp. 399–439, esp. 402–403.

[39] See the introduction to my edition, Marsilio Ficino: The Philebus Commentary (Berkeley, Los Angeles, London, 1975; reprint 1979, with corrections), pp. 3–15, 48–56.

[40] On the 1484 edition and its preparation, see Kristeller, Supplementum 1:cxlvii–clvii; idem, "The First Printed Edition of Plato's Works and the Date of Its Publication (1484)," in Science and History: Studies in Honor of Edward Rosen , ed. Erna

Hilfstein, Pawel Czartoryski, and Frank D. Grande (Wroclaw, 1978), pp. 25–35; Gentile in Mostra , pp. 117–119 (no. 91); and Hankins, Plato in the Italian Renaissance 1:300–311, 2:465–482 (app. 18). For its later fortunes, see also John Monfasani. "For the History of Marsilio Ficino's Translation of Plato: The Revision Mistakenly Attributed to Ambrogio Flandino, Simon Grynaeus' Revision of 1532, and the Anonymous Revision of 1556/1557," Rinascimento , 2d ser., 27 (1987), 293–299. For the astrological significance of 1484 itself, see Chapter 3, n. 1 below.


22

Eventually in 1496 he assembled five long commentaries together with chapter breakdowns and summaries in one volume—those on the Timaeus, Philebus, Parmenides, Sophist, and Phaedrus (though two of them only can be said to be complete). To these he added a commentary focusing on the "fatal" number in the eighth book of the Republic , and dedicated the resulting collection to Niccolò Valori.[41] It is

[41] Kristeller Supplementum 1:cxvii–cxxiii, clv; Marcel, Marsile Ficin , pp. 521–533; Gentile in Mostra , pp. 155–156 (no. 120). For Ficino's admiration in general for, and indebtedness to, the Valori family (Filippo, Niccolò's older brother who died in 1494, had been the financier of the 1484 Plato edition), see the Commentaria 's proem to Niccolò, f. lv (= Opera , p. 1136.2).

We know from a letter to Uranius of 18 Jan. 1493 that Ficino composed his De Sole in the course of the summer of 1492 and followed it with the De Lumine . Marcel claims that it was at this juncture that Ficino wrote the De Numero Fatali —"après la République , qui lui avait inspiré le De Sole et sans doute, dans le mème temps l'Expositio circa numerum nuptialem "—before taking up his Timaeus Commentary again on 7 Nov. 1492 (pp. 530–531). However, Ficino's references in the De Numero Fatali to the Timaeus Commentary suggest otherwise. Indeed, on the twin grounds that the De Numero Fatali is not referred to elsewhere in Ficino's writings (whereas the Timaeus Commentary is) and that it is printed in the Commentaria volume after the colophon, Kristeller has argued that it was written as late as 1496 or "a little before" (Supplementum 1:cxx–cxxi, cxxiii).

Corsi's Vita Marsilii Ficini , which has been edited by Marcel in his Marsile Ficin , pp. 680–689, cannot be relied upon, as Kristeller has demonstrated in his Studies in Renaissance Thought and Letters (Rome 1956; reprint 1985), pp. 191–211. Corsi's chapter 14 is particularly confusing: it asserts that in the last seven years of his life, "having finished [editis cannot mean 'published' here] what he had written on the fatal number of Plato in the eighth book of the Republic , and then the De Sole and the De Lumine , Ficino began new commentaries on the whole of Plato. . . . In this year [1492], after he had completed his extremely learned commentaries on the Parmenides and the Timaeus and also most of his commentary on Dionysius' Mystical Theology , he then wrote and finished his commentary on the Divine Names . But in that last period, besides commentaries on the Parmenides and Timaeus , he also wrote (edidit ) his commentaries on the Theaetetus, Philebus, Phaedrus, and Sophist " (I have modified the English translation given by the Members of the School of Economic Science, London, in an appendix to their third volume of The Letters of Marsilio Ficino (London, 1981), pp. 142–143—hereafter Letters ). Four volumes of this admirable series have appeared so far, rendering Ficino's books 1, 3, 4, and 5 respectively.

The unique codex of the De Numero Fatali —the Bayerische Staatsbibliothek's Clm 956b—was apparently made from the 1496 edition, since it is dated Nuremberg 1501 by the transcriber Hartmann Schedel (1440–1514), "doctor of arts and of medicine" and the author of the Liber Chronicarum of Nuremberg; see Kristeller, Supplementum 1:xxxv. I have included its readings in my apparatus in Part Two below.

(footnote continued on the next page)


23

Ficino's only full-length treatise devoted to the Republic , despite the work's prominence for him and in the Neoplatonic tradition; and it is remarkable that its subject should be the "fatal" number and not the allegory of the Cave, the myth of Er, the figure of the Divided Line, or the Idea of the Good—the "set pieces" of other more famous books. Nonetheless, the essay is an anomalous inclusion in the 1496 volume insofar as it is not a commentary upon an entire dialogue but rather a largely self-contained discussion of the issues raised by just a few lines in that dialogue. Perhaps Ficino felt he had covered the general territory of the Republic sufficiently in the course of his quite lengthy epitomes (no epitome exists for book 8, though the argumentum functions as such).[42]

The 1496 volume was apparently in lieu of a deluxe revised edition of the 1484 Plato volume, which Ficino had envisaged before Lorenzo's death on 8 April 1492 and the expulsion of the Medici in the November of 1494, and which he had hoped would include even more extensive commentaries on many, if not on all, of the dialogues as well as revised translations and chapter breakdowns and summaries. Those for the five dialogues, incidentally, include further revisions for Ficino's Plato translations; and the volume concludes with a corrigenda list that occasionally corrects these revisions! In the event, the Commentaria in Platonem was to be the terminus of his specifically Platonic labors, since the last three or so years of his life were devoted to lecturing on and analyzing Saint Paul's Epistles and notably the Epistle to the Romans.[43]

Even as late as 1496, however, Ficino was still uncharacteristically circumspect about Plato's intentions, as one can see from his prefacing expositio . He writes,

The prodigious enigmas of this chapter above [i.e., 546A–D] have terrified me and indeed other Platonists too for a long time from trying to explicate them. Nevertheless, the things in it that I am relatively sure about—having thought about the passage for many years—I will deal with first. At the end I shall take the plunge and deal with what is merely probable. The totally inexplicable I will omit altogether. For Plato wanted [only] certain things to be

[42] Opera , pp. 1396–1438. The dispositio that follows the proem to Niccolò (Opera , p. 1136.3) makes no mention of the De Numero Fatali in its list of the five companion commentaries and the order in which Ficino has chosen to present them. See Gentile in Mostra , p. 156.

[43] Opera , pp. 425–472; Kristeller, Supplementum 1:lxxxi–lxxxii. He only got as far as the first few chapters. For a study, see Walter Dress, Die Mystik des Marsilio Ficino (Berlin and Leipzig, 1929), pp. 151 ff.


24

explained. Words that men cannot understand, however, he justly attributed to the Muses—to the Muses at play—for what is hidden is something playful.

This is a revealing set of provisos and caveats. First it suggests that Ficino had carefully pondered the challenges of the "prodigious" chapter and deliberately postponed commenting upon it as long as possible, or at least until he had garnered a number of insights into its enigmas. In this regard we should note the emendations to his translation of the chapter for the 1484 Plato edition—particularly of the phrasing at note 16 of the apparatus criticus to Text 2 on p. 163 below—bearing in mind that his exemplar remained the Laurenziana's Greek manuscript 85.9.[44]

Second, besides the "fatal" number, Ficino is predictably concerned with the number known in the Pythagorean manner, as we have seen, as the "nuptial" number because of its importance in Plato's advocacy of eugenics; and, in dealing with both numbers, he consciously prepares us to move from the certain, to the probable, to the inexplicable. Elsewhere, notably in the Vita Platonis which prefaces the 1484 Plato edition,[45] and in the Platonic Theology 17.4,[46] he had spoken of

[44] See n. 32 above. The Oxford text by John Burnet, which I shall refer to throughout, lists authoritative variants but does not take into account, since it does not really need to, the subsidiary manuscript tradition utilized by Ficino. It does not list in other words the 85.9 variants. See Appendix 1 below.

[45] Opera , p. 766.2 (the close of the section Libri Platonis ); trans. in Letters 3:38, "What Plato discusses in his Letters , in the books of the Laws , and in the Epinomis , using himself as a speaker, he means us to take as certainties; but what he says in the rest of the dialogues, when he uses Socrates or Timaeus or Parmenides or Zeno as speakers, he wishes us to understand as only resembling the truth."

[46] Ed. Marcel, 3:168–169, 174. Here Ficino argues that three pieces of evidence argue against Plato's having accepted certain Pythagorean tenets: first, he depicts the same people in the process of debating issues they had earlier pronounced on; second, he portrays an indecisive (ambiguus ) Socrates who is reporting on what he has heard (though he himself knows only that he knows nothing); and third, Plato never confirmed when he was old what he had earlier written on Pythagorean beliefs. Indeed, Ficino concludes, "in the Laws , written at an advanced age and the sole work where Plato speaks in his own person, he affirms nothing like these beliefs. Moreover, in the letter to the king Dionysius [i.e., the Second Letter at 314C], written when he was very old, he says that he had never written anything himself about matters divine and that he would never do so. It was as if he were not revealing his own mind to us but describing another's. In the letter to the Syracusans [i.e., the Seventh Letter at 341C], written afterwards when he was even older, he repeated the same opinions and added that no one existed then or would ever exist in the future who would know what Plato thought about such matters; and this was appropriate since he never wrote about them" (pp. 168–169). Ficino concludes the seventeenth book by saying that "Plato affirmed only those views about matters divine which he approved of in the Letters and the Laws ";

and that this did not include Pythagorean theories concerning the "infinite circuits of souls." What he described as the inventions of the ancient theologians in his other dialogues he must have considered "probabilities rather than certainties." Hence Ficino is moved to interpret Plato's words figuratively (longe aliter quam verba designent ). See Hankins, Plato in the Italian Renaissance , pp. 339–340.


25

Plato as habitually presenting us with the merely probable and as declining to promulgate certainties or dogmas. Only in the Laws (which for him included the Epinomis as an epilogue) and the Letters , the last works of Plato's career, does he see him prepared to commit himself publicly, and even then with regard to just three deeply held convictions: that Providence exists; that the soul is immortal; and that there is a scheme of reward and punishment in the afterlife for the good deeds we have effected or the sins we have committed in this life, in other words that a divine justice presides over all things.[47]

Finally, Ficino makes an ambiguous reference to the Muses, something, significantly, that he elects to do again at the very end of his commentary: "But we have debated enough in the company of Plato and the Muses as they play with a serious and inextricable matter." While we might point to similar statements in the Parmenides Commentary for instance,[48] in no other commentary do we find Ficino quite so candidly admitting that he has failed to unravel completely, or to his full satisfaction, the complexities of a Pythagorean-Platonic mystery, failed to penetrate to the core of the sapiential fruit. In none, moreover, do we find him more attuned to the seriocomic tone, to the presence of a mystagogic irony and obliquity in Plato's style and presentation. By way of explanation, he warns us in the prefatory expositio that we must remember that Plato had decided from the beginning to remain silent on certain issues: "certain things Plato himself chose not to unfold" ("quaedam noluit explicari"). The old Pytha-

[47] In his epitome for Laws 1 (Opera , p. 1488.2), in the course of arguing that Plato had "tempered" and reconciled Pythagorean contemplation with Socratic action and had made the one more humanly accessible and the other more adapted to converting us to matters divine and eternal, Ficino maintains that the Republic is more Pythagorean and more Socratic than the Laws , which is more truly Platonic. Plato wrote the latter "so that men who cannot climb the arduous mountain may at least not reject the path to the gentler foothills." For Plato's threefold debt to Heraclitus, to the Pythagoreans (including Parmenides), and to Socrates, see Diogenes Laertius, Lives of the Philosophers 3.8, and Ficino's Vita Platonis (Opera , pp. 764.1, 769.3; trans. in Letters 3:34,45); also my article, "Marsilio Ficino on Plato's Pythagorean Eye," MLN 97 (1982), 171–182.

[48] See my "The Second Ficino-Pico Controversy: Parmenidean Poetry, Eristic and the One," in Marsilio Ficino e il ritorno di Platone: Studi e documenti , ed. Gian Carlo Garfagnini, 2 vols. (Florence, 1986), 2:417–455, with further references.


26

gorean commitment to silence is assumed to be Plato's too, for all his volubility and eloquence.[49]

Marsilio, however, was committed by his expository program to unfolding as much as he possibly could about Plato's most obscure passage in the Republic , and when he sat down he produced something that was for him—a constitutionally digressive and endlessly parenthetical and repetitive thinker—a passably compact, organized, and self-contained treatise. By the time he had reached his conclusion, moreover, he was convinced that he had resolved some at least of Plato's enigmas. Above all he had established a value for the fatal geometric number.

In the course of his inquiry, as we shall see, he also raised a number of questions of abiding interest to scholars both of the Platonic tradition and of Renaissance conceptions of man, of history, and of time, questions that as historians we are drawn to set against the backdrop of Florentine religion and politics at the close of the fifteenth century. For Plato's ideal city brought low by the fatal number prefigures a Florence inflamed by the Savonarolan reform movement with its apocalyptic predictions that an aeon was coming to an end. Ficino was certainly personally affected by the convulsive millenarianism of the 1490s, and brooding on the numbers of time and its dreadful passing was a preoccupation he undoubtedly shared with many of his friends and compatriots, quite apart from the professional astrologers and the self-appointed prophets, in those turbulent, unhappy years preceding the calamità .[50]

More particularly, as a Platonist, he had by then been immersed in the canon for some thirty years and become thoroughly familiar with its allusions to a cyclical time in such works as the Statesman , the Timaeus , and the third book of the Laws . He had become convinced too that Plato had been a reformer and prophet, who had called for change in the polities of Athens and Syracuse, and had predicted, from the Neoplatonic viewpoint at least, the return of the age of gold.[51] However, his acquaintance with Christian, and specifically with Au-

[49] The distinction between Plato's deliberate silence and Plato's playful veiling of mysteries is understandably somewhat unstable.

[50] In Lo zodiaco della vita (Bari, 1976), pp. 18–19—a marvelous study poorly translated by Carolyn Jackson et al. as Astrology in the Renaissance: The Zodiac of Life (London, 1983)—Eugenio Garin observes that the Quattrocento Italian Platonists were to insist on the fatal decline of republics even as they debated the possibility of renewal and return. But were republicans or Platonists more sensitive to this issue than others?

[51] See his Vita Platonis (Opera , pp. 769.3–770; trans. in Letters 3:45–46).


27

gustinian, historiography and with Joachimite prophecy had also exposed him to the contrary notion of a linear time with its successions: the reigns of nature, law, and grace; the four monarchies of Daniel 2:31–45 and 7:17–27; the six historical epochs as defined, for instance, in Augustine's City of God 22.30; the seven kingdoms of Revelation 17.10—the Jesse tree of durations, however numbered, in the history of man and his generations. How then to reconcile the two, since, given his Platonic (and we might add his humanist) assumptions, he was unwilling to accept Augustine's outright rejection in the City of God 12.14 of a cyclical dimension to time? I shall suggest in Chapter 4 that, a syncretist by temperament, he seems to have been drawn rather to the notion of a third temporal order as it were mediating between us and eternity: a spiraling providential time that governs alike the cyclical realm of the stars and the transitory linear history of the sublunar realm that gazes on and depends upon those stars.

Fundamental in this regard is the haunting presence in his mind not only of Hesiod's myth of the golden age and the possibility of its return[52] —predictably so, given Plato's own allusion to Hesiod at the close of his description of the fatal number at 546E ff.—but also, and more importantly, of the myth of the Demiurge in the Timaeus and of the mathematical and musical formulas presented there for the composition of the World-Soul.[53] For this creation myth, which problematizes for us the dualism of other prominent dialogues such as the Phaedo , presented Ficino with a Plato who was a visionary historian, an Attic Moses in Numenius's memorable phrase, whose intuitive, whose prophetic intelligence had been granted an insight both into the actual numbers of time, and thus into their concomitant geometrical figures and ratios, and into the numerical Ideas according to which the Demiurge and his sons had first fashioned a spatiotemporal reality in the image of the true and the good.

[52] Christian commentators often glossed this myth by adverting to the description of the statue with head of gold, breast and arms of silver, belly and thighs of brass, legs of iron, and feet of clay in Daniel 2:31–33.

[53] Since the Old Academy this had been a matter of debate, and the solutions formulated can be found in the following texts: Timaeus Locrus, De Natura Mundi et Animae 96A–C (ed. Marg, pp. 124–130); Plutarch, De Animae Procreatione in Timaeo 1027E ff. (ed. Cherniss, pp. 266–320); Calcidius, Timaeus (ed. Waszink, 81.19–103.12); Proclus, In Timaeum 2.167 .24–193.6 (ed. Diehl, trans. Festugière-Mugler 3.212–239). These are Bertier's references, p. 102, n. 5 (see n. 74 below).


28

In order to arrive at an understanding of Ficino's determination of the fatal number, we must eventually tread some unfamiliar mathematical ground. For an introduction to his approach to Platonic mathematics and to its close links with harmonics and therefore with music and astronomy, we cannot do better, however, than to turn to a concluding section of his epitome for the Epinomis . Ficino thought of this apocryphal dialogue—the author is probably Philip of Opus or another member of the early Academy[54] —as Plato's authentic appendix to the Laws (as its name suggests), and therefore as being endowed with the singular and august authority he attributed to Plato's last work.[55] It has a particular pertinence here in that earlier at 978B ff. the Athenian Stranger had been held to assert that the origin of our sense of numbers derives from our gazing up at the night sky and especially at the changing countenance of the Moon.[56] The Epinomis epitome was probably written in the early 1470s and provides us with a general framework for an understanding of Ficino's more advanced treatment of individual topics in the commentaries on the Timaeus and eventually in the De Numero Fatali .

He is epitomizing the section (990C–991B) on the progression from arithmetic to geometry and then to stereometry.[57] To begin with, he writes, numbers are "in themselves incorporeal" (990C), because they "are nothing other than the number 1 repeated" and 1 is indivisible and therefore without body. Following a Pythagorean formula (found, for instance, in Aristotle's De Caelo 1.1.268a7 ff. and De Anima 1.2.404b21 ff. and repeated throughout antiquity and the Middle Ages), Ficino proceeds to plot number geometrically as first a point, then a line, then a plane (superficies ), and finally a volume (profundum ). Hence there are three kinds of divisible numbers after the one as the indivisible point: linear, planar, and solid. Thus the doubling of 1 makes the linear 2, which in turn becomes the square 4 and eventually the cube 8 (991A).

[54] Diogenes Laertius, Lives of the Philosophers 3.37, writes, "It is said Philippus was the author of the Epinomis ." See Leonardo Tarán, Academica: Plato, Philip of Opus, and the Pseudo-Platonic Epinomis , Memoirs of the American Philosophical Society, vol. 107 (Philadelphia, 1976), pp. 133–139.

[55] See, for example, his Vita Platonis (Opera , p. 766.2; trans. in Letters 3:38), his epitome for the Epinomis itself (Opera , p. 1525.2—the heading), his epitome for the Laws I (Opera , p. 1488.2), and his Platonic Theology 4.1 and 17.4 (ed. Marcel, 1:165, 3:168–169).

[56] Cf. the Timaeus' s contention at 47A ff. that the sun, moon, planets, and stars were created in order to instill in us a sense of time and number (repeated by Diogenes Laertius in his Lives of the Philosophers 3.74).

[57] Opera , pp. 1529–1530. In the 1491 Venice edition of the Platonis Opera Omnia , the epitome (argumentum ) is found on fols. 323v–324v (sigs. R3v–R4v).


29

The perfect proportion or ratio[58] is the double, and this "contains all the [other] proportions within itself." In effect, Ficino is concerned only with the three primary ratios that govern both music and the cosmos: those of the double (for us the ratio of 2:1), of the sesquialteral (i.e., of one and a half to one—the ratio of 3:2), and of the sesquitertial (i.e., of one and a third to one—the ratio of 4:3). These ratios he sees Plato deriving from the first four numbers, the Pythagoreans' tetraktys, which when added together make up ten. The four numbers, in short, encode two fundamental kinds of relationship: that of being arithmetically equal to and that of being geometrically proportional to. This is self-evident of course, but fraught with Pythagorean and Platonic implications, not least in the spheres of ethics and of politics.[59]

With these primary ratios Ficino moves to the equivalent musical intervals of the diapason, the diapente, and the diatesseron, the "consonances" or harmonic ratios of the octave (2:1), the perfect fifth (3:2), and the perfect fourth (4:3) respectively. And this musical extension leads in turn: first, to the Pythagorean theory of the music of the spheres and the Sirens' song which Plato identified with it in the Republic at 616B–617E, where each Siren sings one of the eight notes of the octave; and, second, to the theory of harmonious proportions governing the cosmos and thus the distances between the Earth, the various planetary spheres, and the firmament of the fixed stars. Hence Ficino sees Plato postulating that "the interval" (with a play upon both the spatial and the musical meanings) from the Earth to the Sun compared to the interval from the Sun to the firmament of the fixed stars is in the proportion of 3:2 to 4:3, the first ratio creating the harmony of the diapente, the second that of the diatesseron. The diatesseron is also the harmony created by the interval between the Earth and the Moon.[60]

[58] The distinction between the two terms is a matter of definition. See Chapter 2 below.

[59] Plutarch, Quaestiones Convivales 8.2 (Moralia 719A–B), notes that Lycurgus had expelled the arithmetical proportion from Lacedaemon as too democratic, and introduced the geometrical as more appropriate to "moderate oligarchy and lawful monarchy"! Antidemocrats could thus argue that their foes were arguing for a system that in fact equalized inequalities. See Plato, Republic 558C, Laws 6.757B, and Gorgias 508A ("geometrical equality is of great importance among gods and men alike"); and Aristotle, Politics 3.5.8, 3.9, 5.1.7, and Nicomachean Ethics 2.6.7.

[60] Ficino turns to the theme of musical and celestial "consonances" in his De Numero Fatali 12. The astronomy and mathematics of the Epinomis should be compared with that in the Laws 7.818–820. For the ratios governing both music and the cosmos, see Aristotle's criticisms in his De Caelo 290b12–291a28 and Macrobius's ac-

account in his In Somnium Scipionis 2.1.1–25 and 2.4.1–10—passages long familiar to Ficino, who thought of a harmony in the ancient sense as a proper sequence of sounds. See William R. Bowen, "Ficino's Analysis of Musical Harmonia ," in Ficino and Renaissance Neoplatonism , ed. Konrad Eisenbichler and Olga Zorzi Pugliese, University of Toronto Italian Studies, 1 (Ottawa, 1986), pp. 17–27; and in general S. K. Heninger, Jr., Touches of Sweet Harmony: Pythagorean Cosmology and Renaissance Poetics (San Marino, Calif., 1974), pp. 91–104, 115–132, with further references.


30

These summary remarks are sufficient for us to see the nature for Ficino of the inextricable links between number theory, geometry, harmonics, and Chaldaean-Ptolemaic cosmology. He had inherited these directly of course from Plato and then from the Neoplatonists, but also from the medieval tradition and more particularly from his youthful study of Calcidius's commentary on the Timaeus.[61] The web of debts and influences may be a complicated one, but it is all of a piece.

The Epinomis epitome also emphasizes, as do many other passages in Ficino's commentaries, the Platonic significance of the number 12, 12 being the number of the world spheres—the eight celestial and the four elementary—in the Chaldaean system which Plato inherited.[62] Under the World-Soul, Ficino writes, there are twelve souls for the twelve spheres, and within each sphere there are twelve orders of rational souls. In the eight celestial spheres we find the eight orders of souls of the constellations and stars; on earth, the one order of men (and we might add of the lowest daemons); and in the aether (fire), air, and water, the three orders of the higher daemons. From the onset, that is, there is a dramatic contrast between the fingers-and-toes world of 10 and the duodecimal world of the rational souls, divine, daemonic, and human, encompassing as it does the primary ratios and musical harmonies.

Before entering further into an account of the duodecimal mysteries Ficino saw at the heart of the Republic' s reference to a geometric number, I think it useful to conclude this opening chapter with a review of the ancient texts Ficino probably turned to for guidance, though none of them is a source as such, since none of them provided

[61] See my "Ficino's Interpretation of Plato's Timaeus ," pp. 404–408.

[62] The Epinomis does not discuss twelve as such, but it does treat of the cosmic nest of spheres: of the eight celestial spheres at 986A ff. and of the elementary spheres at 981C ff. Aether is defined in this dialogue as intermediate between fire and air—e.g., at 984B ff.—and Ficino does not count it as a separate substance. Aristotle's view was of course quite different.


31

him with "the answer."[63] Ironically, the one Neoplatonic treatise he would surely have been most excited and convinced by, Proclus's thirteenth treatise in his Republic Commentary, was completely unknown to him and to his contemporaries, as we shall see; and the work he looked to most consistently for help with Platonic mathematics, a treatise by Theon of Smyrna, a Middle Platonist, has nothing whatsoever to say about Plato's great mathematical crux.[64] In fact, Ficino's best guides remained the other texts of Plato himself, as our analysis of the Epinomis epitome has already in part indicated, though Auguste Diès has suggested, perversely, that Plato may have wanted to throw his readers off the scent by endowing technical terms here with different meanings than he had allotted them elsewhere.[65]

As always with a medieval and Renaissance scholar, the question of "sources" is complicated; in Ficino's case particularly so, given his eclectic methods and wide scholarship, his continual reworking of ideas and motifs throughout his life, his recourse at times to secondary guides—compendia, epitomes, and digests—and on occasions his failure (or perhaps his refusal even) to identify his authorities, let alone his specific sources. One should add, however, that his scholarly standards, if we compare them with those of the majority of his contemporaries, were exceptionally rigorous.

We know by virtue of his explicit reference that he knew Theon of Smyrna's three-book (originally apparently five-book) treatise, Expositio Rerum Mathematicarum ad Legendum Platonero Utilium , an elementary work in Greek on arithmetic and the types of numbers, and on the theory of musical harmony and astronomy. It is valuable for its citations from a number of pre-Euclidean mathematicians, and notably for its long passages quoted verbatim from Adrastus of Aphrodisias and Thrasyllus. Indeed, John Dillon asserts that it is "essentially a compilation from these two immediate sources."[66] Dating from the

[63] For a comprehensive index testimoniorum for 546A–D, see Boter, Textual Tradition , pp. 345–346. Perhaps half of these would have been unknown, however, to Ficino and his contemporaries.

[64] Diès, Essai , p. 11, remarks, "Il est presque étonnant de voir combien sont rares et maigres, en dehors de Proclus, les allusions ou commentaires des anciens relativement au Nombre de Platon." But see n. 63 above.

[65] Essai , pp. 132 ff., with a list of such terms.

[66] The Middle Platonists, 80B.C. to A.D. 220 (London and Ithaca, N.Y., 1977), pp. 397–399 at 397; Theon's "borrowings" have been known for some time. See also Michel, De Pythagore , pp. 119–120, and Diés, Essai , p. 28. This is not the Theon of the late fourth or early fifth century A.D. who was Hypatia's father (Vita Isid . fr. 104; see R. T. Wallis, Neoplatonism [London, 1972], p. 139).


32

first half of the second century A.D. , it is usually referred to by its Latin title simply as the Expositio .[67] We can deduce, furthermore, from a notice in a letter Ficino wrote to Angelo Poliziano on 6 September 1474 or shortly thereafter,[68] that sometime before that Ficino had translated the first part of the Expositio into Latin, though he never published the translation and had probably never intended to publish it. It has only survived, albeit anonymously, in the Vatican library's MS Vat. lat. 4530, fols. 119–151, and in Hamburg's Staats- und Universitätsbibliothek's MS cod. philol. 305, fols. 139–191v (a manuscript that was copied from the Vatican MS by Lucas Holstenius in the seventeenth century).[69] Though anonymous, the Expositio follows in both manuscripts upon a Latin version, which has been convincingly attributed to Ficino, of Iamblichus's De Secta Pythagorica Libri Quattuor , a collection of four treatises consisting of the De Vita Pythagorica , the Protrepticus , the De Communi Mathematica Scientia , and the In Nicomachi Arithmeticam Introductionem .[70] In Sebastiano Gen-

[67] It was edited by Eduardus Hiller for Teubner in 1878 and by Dupuis, with a French translation, in 1892 (see n. 4 above). The text has come down to us in bad condition; see J. Gilbart Smyly, "Notes on Theon of Smyrna," Hermathena 33 (1907), 261–279, who offers fourteen emendations to Hiller's edition. There is an English translation from Dupuis by Robert and Deborah Lawlor entitled Mathematics Useful for Understanding Plato (San Diego, 1979).

[68] Ed. Sebastiano Gentile, Marsilio Ficino: Lettere I: Epistolarum Familiarium Liber I (Florence, 1990), pp. cclix, 44–45 (no. 20); trans. in Letters 1:59–60 (no. 21). See also Kristeller, Supplementum 1:1.

[69] Kristeller, Supplementum 1:xxx–xxxi, xl–xli, cxlvi–cxlvii, 1, 3; idem, Ficino and His Work , pp. 90 (sub Hamburg, cod. phil. 305), 108 (sub Vatican, Vat. lat. 4530), and 136 (no. 37); Sebastiano Gentile, "Sulle prime traduzioni dal greco di Marsilio Ficino," Rinascimento , 2d ser., 30 (1990), 57–104 at 74n. The Vatican MS is written in the hand of Elia del Medigo with a few notes by Pier Leoni da Spoleto, Lorenzo's learned, bibliophile physician; it was once possessed and annotated by Giovanni Pico della Mirandola. The Hamburg MS has been missing, according to Kristeller, since World War II.

[70] Ficino probably worked from one or both of the Laurenziana's Greek MSS. 86.3 and 86.29 (which was copied from 86.3). See Kristeller, Supplementum 1:xxx, xl–xlii, cxlv–cxlvi; idem, Ficino and His Work , pp. 74–75 (sub Laur. 86.3 and 86.29), and 136 (no. 35); Martin Sicherl, "Platonismus und Textüberlieferung," in Griechische Kodikologie und Textüberlieferung , ed. Dieter Harlfinger (Darmstadt, 1980), p. 555; and Gentile in Mostra , pp. 32–34 (no. 24—the Laurenziana's 86.29). The contents-list of MS. 86.3 gives us the titles of five more treatises in what Iamblichus must have intended to be a kind of Pythagorean encyclopedia; see D. J. O'Meara, Pythagoras Revived: Mathematics and Philosophy in Late Antiquity (Oxford, 1989), part 1, esp. pp. 91–101.

Apart from MS Vat. lat. 4530 (and its Hamburg copy), Ficino's Latin version of the De Secta Pythagorica also survives in the Vatican's MS Vat. lat. 5953, which was copied by Luca Fabiani and owned by Pier Leoni; though lacking the Theon, it includes

Ficino's translation of Hermias and other texts and of his Philebus Commentary. See Kristeller, Supplementum 1:xli–xlii; idem, Ficino and His Work , pp. 108 (sub Vat. lat. 5953), 136 (no. 35); Gentile in Mostra , p. 33; idem, "Sulle prime traduzioni," pp. 73–74 and 80n (with a listing of the more glaring omissions in the De Vita Pythagorica rendering—first noted by H. Pistelli in 1893—and of some of the far fewer omissions in the renderings of the other treatises).

There is no modern edition, incidentally, either of Ficino's Theon translation or of his De Secta Pythagorica (which I consulted only in MS. 4530).


33

tile's words there is no doubting the Theon translation's "paternità ficiniana."[71] Moreover, if Gentile is correct in arguing that the "translations" of the treatises constituting the De Secta Pythagorica show the telltale signs of being among Ficino's earliest attempts (being too literal and at the same time inexact) and that they were therefore probably written prior to 1464,[72] then it would suggest a similarly early dating for the Theon translation, even though our first notice of it is in the Poliziano letter. I have placed "translations" in quotation marks, however, because my own cursory examination of Ficino's rendering of the In Nicomachi Arithmeticam encountered paraphrasing, summarizing, and some omissions (though not on the scale of that found in the De Vita Pythagorica ). Thus, we should probably think of the Iamblichus collection not just as an early but as a personal, working translation only; and this may also be true, as Gentile has suggested, of Ficino's work on Theon. The question awaits further investigation. Presumably, Ficino's copy text for the Expositio was the Laurenziana's 85.9, folios 12v–26r, part of the huge codex he had received from Cosimo de' Medici in 1462 containing the Plato text he was to use principally for his great translation.73

Another parallel resource for Ficino might have been the better organized but less sophisticated treatise, again in Greek, by the Neopythagorean Nicomachus of Gerasa (who probably flourished also in the first half of the second century A.D. ), the two-book Arithmetica Introductio . Nevertheless, this too has nothing specific to say about Plato's number except for a passing allusion at 2.24.11 to the effect that some of the things Nicomachus has just discussed are best illuminated by Plato in the passage in the Republic (i.e., at 546A ff.).[74] The

[71] Mostra , p. 30; also "Sulle prime traduzion," p. 74.

[72] Mostra , pp. 33–34; also "Sulle prime traduzioni," pp. 75–76.

[73] Kristeller, Ficino and His Work , p. 136 (no. 37); and Gentile in Mostra , pp. 29–30.

[74] Ed. Ricardus Hoche (Leipzig, 1866), p. 131.11–14. There is an English translation by Martin Luther D'Ooge, with a long and useful introduction under the head-

ing "Studies on Greek Mathematics" by Frank Egleston Robbins and Louis Charles Karpinski, entitled Nicomachus of Gerasa: Introduction to Arithmetic , University of Michigan Studies, Humanities Series, vol. 16 (New York, 1926; 2d ed., 1972). It contains some suggested emendations to the Hoche edition on pp. 158–166 and on pp. 37–43 a tabular comparison of Nicomachus's work with Theon's. Helpful too is the French translation and commentary by Janine Bertier, Nicomaque de Gérase: Introduction arithmétique (Paris, 1978); and George Johnson, The Arithmetical Philosophy of Nicomachus of Gerasa (Lancaster, Pa., 1916).


34

Introductio was translated into Latin by Apuleius, according to a notice by Cassiodorus, though the translation has not survived.[75] The work was apparently unknown to the younger but still contemporary Theon, but was commented upon expansively by Iamblichus in one of his "Pythagorean" treatises, the In Nicomachi Arithmeticam,[76] and therefore translated with the others by Ficino, as we have seen. It was also commented upon by Philoponus, by Sotericos, and by Asclepius of Tralles; and it was translated, paraphrased, expanded here and condensed there by Boethius in his De Institutione Arithmetica , and reproduced in part and more distantly by Martianus Capella, Isidore of Seville, and Cassiodorus.[77] In fact, Ficino's vague allusion to Boethius at one point may be to the De Institutione Arithmetica in general or specifically to 2.46 (which is rendering Nicomachus's Introductio 2.24.11 and therefore refers to Plato's "nuptial" passage in the Republic 8); however, it could equally well be to Boethius's De Institutione Musica or to various passages in his many commentaries on Aristotle.[78]

Finally, there is the possibility that he might have known the anonymous Theologumena Arithmeticae , which includes notice of Nicomachus's views.[79] This is often attributed to Iamblichus but may indeed be by Nicomachus; for Nicomachus certainly wrote a treatise of

[75] In De Artibus ac Disciplinis Liberalium Litterarum , chapter 4, De Arithmetica . See Migne's Patrologia Latina 70.1208B.

[76] Ed. Hermenegildus Pistelli (Leipzig, 1894), rev. Udalricus Klein (Stuttgart, 1975). For a summary, see Robbins in D'Ooge, Nicomachus , pp. 126–131.

[77] See Robbins and Karpinski in D'Ooge, Nicomachus , pp. 132–142; also Bertier, Nicomaque , p. 9.

[78] The De Institutione Arithmetica and the De Institutione Musica were edited together by Gottfried Friedlein (Leipzig, 1867). The reference at 2.46 (p. 151.22–25) in the former reads: "Hoc autem facilius cognoscitur ex lectione Platonis in libris de republica eo loco, qui nuptialis dicitur, quem ex persona musarum philosophus introducit." In general see Michel, De Pythagore , pp. 134–136.

[79] Ed. Victorius de Falco (Leipzig, 1922). There is an English translation by Robin Waterfield entitled The Theology of Arithmetic: On the Mystical, Mathematical and Cosmological Symbolism of the First Ten Numbers (Grand Rapids, Mich., 1988).


35

that name.[80] Interestingly, a manuscript containing the Theologumena appears in the Laurenziana as Plut. 71.30. It has notations by Poliziano (though these are not on the Theologumena , which appears on fols. 92–145) and was copied apparently from a manuscript of Bessarion's now in the Marciana as Marc. gr. 234 (667).[81] The two manuscripts and others assuredly testify to the awareness at least of the text in Platonic circles.

We should also recall a tradition surely known to Ficino from Marinus's Vita Procli 28 to the effect that Proclus claimed to be the reincarnation of Nicomachus's soul, having been born 216 years after Nicomachus's death. Two hundred and sixteen years is the Pythagorean number assigned to the interval between lives, since it is the cube of 6 and also the sum of the cubes of the three numbers of the perfect Pythagorean triangle, i.e., of 3, 4, and 5.[82] This would effectively invest Nicomachus with Proclus's authority, or at least validate his status as a Platonist-Pythagorean. Nevertheless, Ficino never mentions him anywhere in his Opera even though he must have known of him.

In the argumentum for the Republic book 8, having dismissed Theon, Ficino dismisses Iamblichus also, declaring that although Iamblichus had tried to unravel Plato's knot, he had only succeeded in making it the tighter. This is an explicit reference either to Iamblichus's In Nicomachi Arithmeticam 82.20–24, 83.13–18, or, more probably, to his De Vita Pythagorica 27.130–131, though in neither passage does Iamblichus determine Plato's number.[83]

[80] Compare, for instance, De Falco's attribution to Iamblichus with Bertier's to Nicomachus (p. 9). Friedrich Ast, who edited the Theologumena in 1817 along with Nicomachus's Introductio , rejected Nicomachus's authorship without accepting Iamblichus's (p. 157); while Robbins in D'Ooge, Nicomachus , pp. 82–87, argued it was basically Nicomachean even if Iamblichus was its compiler.

De Falco's apparatus adduces numerous parallels between the Theologumena and the treatises and commentaries by Nicomachus, Theon, Iamblichus, and several others, including Proclus's In Timaeum .

[81] De Falco, p. v.

[82] John M. Dillon, "A Date for the Death of Nicomachus of Gerasa," Classical Review 19 (1969), 274–275. Note that the Theologumena claims in the section on the hexad that certain Pythagoreans had declared that Pythagoras himself was reincarnated every 216 years (trans. Waterfield, pp. 83–84). See Dupuis, Nombre , p. 54. In the Republic 8 at 546C6, "hekaton de kubôn triados ," Plato himself may be alluding to 216 (as the cube of 6 as 1+2+3); cf. Schneider, Platonis Opera Graece 3:xxxi. It is also of course the product of multiplying the first two cubes, 8 and 27, the "feet" of the Timaeus 's lambda.

[83] MS Vat. lat. 4530 renders neither of these passages into Latin. Indeed, Ficino is barely summarizing the larger contexts in which they appear.

In the De Vita Pythagorica 27.130–131 Iamblichus asserts that Pythagoras "constructed, as it were, three lines, representing forms of government, and connected them at the ends to make a right-angled triangle: one side has the nature of the epitritos, the hypotenuse measures five, and the third is in the middle of the other two. If we calculate the angles at which the lines meet, and the squares on each side, we have an excellent model of a constitution. Plato appropriated this idea, when he expressly mentioned, in the Republic, the first two numbers in the ratio of four to three which join with the fifth to make the two harmonies" (trans. Gillian Clark, Iamblichus: On the Pythagorean Life [Liverpool, 1989], p. 58). See Clark's note ad loc. on the confusions in the passage, particularly the identification of the side of 3 with "the nature of the epitritos": these may be precisely the confusions that Ficino has in mind. See also Schneider, Platonis Opera Graece 3:xxxiiii–xxxvii, and Diès, Essai , pp. 38–39.

We might note that there is insufficient evidence to determine Iamblichus's views on the Republic , which is mentioned only in passing in the two recent studies on Iamblichus as a commentator on Plato, namely, John M. Dillon's Iamblichi Chalcidensis in Platonis Dialogos Platonis Commentariorum Fragmenta (Leiden, 1973), and Bent Dalsgaard Larsen's Jamblique de Chalcis: Exégète et philosophe (plus supplement, Testimonia et Fragmenta Exegetica ) (Aarhus, 1972).

Iamblichus's De Communi Mathematica Scientia Liber , ed. Nicolaus Festa (Leipzig, 1891; rev. Klein, Stuttgart, 1975) also alludes in various places to Nicomachus, but not to Plato's passage.


36

Ficino probably scanned two other ancient authorities—both of them eminent Platonici in his genealogical tree of the Platonic wisdom—for their views on Plato's celebrated crux, though he only mentions one of them once and in passing in his De Numero Fatali .

In his notable essay, De Iside et Osiride 56 (Moralia 373F ff.), Plutarch (A.D. c. 46–c. 120) speaks of the right-angled scalene triangle so dear to the Pythagoreans, and observes parenthetically that "Plato seems to avail himself of this triangle in the Republic in order to form the nuptial figure (to gamêlion diagramma syntattôn ). In it the vertical side is worth 3, the base 4, and the hypotenuse, whose square equals the sum of the squares of the other two sides, is worth 5." It is "the most beautiful of triangles" to Plutarch (presumably because all three sides are rational whole numbers).[84] This would have certainly confirmed Ficino's assumption, which he derived from Aristotle's gloss, that 12 was the secret key to the Platonic riddle. It also suggests, as Depuis notes, that Plutarch was unfamiliar with any comprehensive interpretation of the passage.[85] Schneider, Dupuis, and others have

[84] Adduced in this context by Schneider, Platonis Opera Graece 3:xxxii; Dupuis, Nombre , p. 19; Adam, Republic , p. 267; and Diès, Essai , p. 25. Plutarch goes on to identify the 3, 4, and 5 respectively with the Egyptian triad of Osiris, Isis, and Horus.

[85] Théon , p. 372. Both Schneider, Platonis Opera Graece 3:xxxiii, and Diès, Essai , pp. 25–26, also cite Plutarch's De Animae Procreatione 10 (Moralia 1017C): "In the Republic , Socrates, when he begins to speak about the number that some refer to as the nuptial number, says: 'A divine object of generation has a period that is comprised by a

perfect number' [546B3–4], what he calls a divine object of generation being nothing other than the universe." But Plutarch then proceeds to define the tetraktys and at 1018C to treat of six as a perfect number which is called "marriage" because of "the commixture of the even and the odd."


37

adduced too a similar passage from the treatise On Music 3.23 by Aristides Quintilianus (probably third or fourth century A.D. ); but it is less likely though not impossible that Ficino had read it. It argues that "the sides of the triangle being 3, 4, and 5, if we take the sum of them, we obtain the number 12; . . . the sides at the right angle are in the relationship of epitritus [4:3], and it is the root of epitritus added to 5 that Plato is referring to [in the Republic ]."[86] The observations here not only speak to the importance of the Pythagoreans' "beautiful" triangle but underscore the importance of the sum of its sides being 12, and the fact that the "root" of epitritus means 3 plus 4. We might note that other Plutarchan essays familiar to Ficino address a variety of related mathematical topics: these include the De Musica 22 on the harmonic means; the De E apud Delphos on the properties of the number 5; and, as we have seen, the De Animae Procreatione in Timaeo Platonis , especially chapters 11–20 and 29–30, on Plato's philosophy of numbers and the harmonic means and intervals.[87]

The second authority, and the most problematic, was certainly Proclus (A.D. 412–485), the Platonist Ficino knew most thoroughly after Plato and Plotinus and to whom he was deeply indebted throughout his career. Indeed, Ficino must have at one time turned to the Successor as his best hope. For he first encountered the opening half of Proclus's huge commentary on the Republic in 1492, after Janus Lascaris had purchased a manuscript of the first twelve treatises in Greece, probably in Crete, and sent it in excellent condition to Florence to Lorenzo's library, where it eventually became the Laurenziana's 80.9.[88] Ficino must have borrowed it almost immediately,

[86] Schneider, Platonis Opera Graece 3:xxxiii, and Dupuis, Théon , p. 372, citing from the edition by Meibom in his Antiquae Musicae Auctores Septem (Amsterdam, 1652), 2:1–164 at 152 (i.e., in the more recent ed. by R. P. Winnington-Ingram, De Musica [Leipzig, 1963], p. 124.25–26). See also Adam, Republic , p. 267, and Diès, Essai , p. 39.

[87] Ed. and trans. Cherniss, pp. 262–321. Michel, De Pythagore , pp. 151–153. See also Schneider, Platonis Opera Graece 3:xxxii.

[88] This is in fact the first half of a single codex of more than four hundred leaves dating from the ninth or tenth century. It was later divided, and by the fifteenth century the first half belonged to a certain Armonios or Harmonios of Athens. See the edition by Wilhelm Kroll, Procli Diadochi in Platonis Rem Publicam Commentarii , 2 vols. (Leipzig, 1899–1901), 1:i–vii; also the French translation by A.-J. Festugière, Proclus: Commentaire sur la République , 3 vols. (Paris, 1970), 2:7–8. Kroll's first volume con-

tains the first twelve treatises, his second the last five. The only allusion in the first twelve treatises to the crucial passage in the Republic 8:546A1–D3 occurs in the seventh treatise at 1:219.10 ff., where Proclus asserts that a state is undermined when its magistrates neglect not so much gymnastics as mousikê , "as Socrates declares in the Sacred Discourse of the Muses."


38

for we have a note attesting to his loan dated 7 July 1492.[89] By as early as 3 August 1492 he had gathered some "flowers" from its "delightful meadows" which he epitomized in a letter to his close friend Martinus Uranius (alias Prenninger) and later published in 1495 in the eleventh book of his Letters .[90] However, from Proclus's massive treatise Ficino received in fact no illumination. For the meadows he had wandered in treat only of the first seven books of the Republic , and Proclus does not deal with the Discourse of the Muses in book 8 until his thirteenth treatise, the Melissa . But this Ficino and his contemporaries could not have known, since the second half of Proclus's commentary—now the Vatican's MS Vat. gr. 2197—did not arrive in the West until years later (how many exactly I cannot discover)[91] and was for all intents and purposes hidden from the scholarly world until the appearance in 1886 of Richard Schoell's edition.[92] Thus, notwithstanding his erudition, Schneider was completely unaware of its existence in 1830, and even more tellingly Dupuis was unaware of it as late as 1881. As Diès observes, "les recherches sur le nombre géométrique de Platon durent se poursuivre, même après la Renaissance,

[89] Kristeller, Ficino and His Work , pp. 73 (sub Laur. 80.9), 125–126; idem, "Proclus as a Reader of Plato and Plotinus, and His Influence in the Middle Ages and the Renaissance," in Proclus: Lecteur et interprète des anciens (Paris, 1987), pp. 191–211 at 203; Gentile in Mostra , pp. 151–152 and plate XXXIV (no. 117—the Laurenziana's 80.9); Viti in Mostra , p. 189 (no. 160).

[90] Opera , pp. 937.2–943.1. See Gentile in Mostra , p. 152; Marcel, Marsile Ficin , pp. 524 ff. For another partial translation, that by Nicolaus Scutellius of Trent in 1526, see Paul Oskar Kristeller, Iter Italicum , 6 vols. (London and Leiden, 1963–1991), 1:409.

[91] It came to the Salviati in Florence (certainly long after Ficino's death) and eventually passed into the hands of the Colonnas, and thence in 1821 to the Vatican. See Diès, Essai , pp. 53–54 (but for "via Cologne" on p. 53 read "via the family of the Colonna"); and John Whittaker, "Varia Procliana," Greek, Roman, and Byzantine Studies 14.4 (1973), 427–428.

[92] Procli Commentariorum in Rempublicam Platonis Partes Ineditae (Berlin, 1886). Schoell edited the only version available to him at the time, a mid-seventeenth-century copy (now the Vatican's MS Barberinianus gr. 65) made by Lucas Holstenius (and in part perhaps by Leo Allatius) of a portion from the Salviati's MS. Two years later J. B. Pitra edited the Vaticanus gr. 2197 directly but badly. It was not, therefore, until Kroll's second volume of 1901 that the last half of Proclus's work was authoritatively edited and reconstructed.


39

comme si Proclus n'eût pas existé."[93] Furthermore, even had Ficino been able to gain access by some stroke of fortune to this second half, his interpretative skills would have been challenged to the utmost, for its leaves, and notably those containing the Melissa , had probably already sustained some at least of their present damage.[94]

While he did not know the pertinent treatise of Proclus's commentary on the Republic , however, he was certainly well acquainted with Proclus's Timaeus Commentary and its detailed analysis of the loci mathematici in that dialogue. Also, it is just possible he had skimmed through Proclus's commentary on the first book of Euclid where there are some obvious references to Plato's passage. The prologue, for instance, declares first that "matters pertaining to powers (dunameis ) . . . whether they be roots or squares . . . Socrates in the Republic puts into the mouth of the loftily-speaking Muses, bringing together in determinate limits the elements common to all mathematical ratios and setting them up in specific numbers by which the periods of fruitful birth and its opposite, unfruitfulness, can be discerned"; and then again that the Republic 's "geometrical number" is "the factor that de-

[93] Diès, Essai , p. 54 (cf. p. 4). Hence Bodin's comment in his 1581 Apologie de René Harpin , f. 41 (and repeated in his 1586 De Republica Libri Sex , p. 412), that Proclus had learnedly interpreted the first seven books of the Republic but demurred before the difficulty of the eighth book where it was a question of numbers—cited in Dupuis, Théon , p. 391, and Diès, Essai , p. 54: "Proclus septem quidem Platonis de Republica libros satis accurate interpretatus octavum attingere noluit, rei difficultate, ut opinor, revocatus."

[94] In 1640 Holstenius was already lamenting its condition, which he blamed on the Salviati, perhaps unjustly. In general all the upper borders are in very bad condition, and accordingly Kroll's text is full of lacunas or conjectural reconstructions. With regard specifically to the thirteenth treatise, missing are the introduction, and the first eight and a half paragraphs of forty-five, though Kroll was able ingeniously to reconstruct the initial two leaves of the introduction from sixteenth-century copies (see his 2:vi, 473, and apparatus for pp. 1–4). Missing, in other words, are the very paragraphs which must have glossed the twenty-three lines (in Burnet's edition) of the Republic 's 546A1–D1 (though it is just possible they were still there in the late fifteenth century). Proclus's detailed commentary currently begins at 2.4.24, glossing 546D2's "ouk euphueis oud' eutucheis paides esontai ."

For the bibliographical complexities, in addition to Kroll's remarks, see Festugière, Proclus: Commentaire sur la République 2:7–8, 105n, 108n; and, more speculatively, Carlo Gallavotti, "Intorno ai Commenti di Proclo alla Repubblica," Bollettino del Comitato per la preparazione dell'edizione nazionale dei classici greci e latini 19 (1971), 41–49. Gallavotti, pp. 45–47, believes that Proclus's commentary consists of six heterogeneous treatises written at different times and with different aims and later collected together.

For accounts of aspects of the Melissa 's exceedingly complex exegesis, which is variously and ambitiously arithmetical, geometrical, musical, astronomical-astrological, cos-

mological, psychological, and dialectical, and for which Proclus was probably indebted in part at least to earlier exegetes, see the appendix by Friedrich Hultsch (himself an important figure in the history of the modern interpretation of Plato's Number) in Kroll's second volume, pp. 384–415; also Diès, Essai , pp. 28–51, and especially 40–51. I have not seen A. G. Laird's Plato's Geometrical Number and the Comment of Proclus (Madison, Wis., 1918). We should note that Proclus has enriched our understanding of the ancient interpretative tradition for this passage by referring to a number of authorities necessarily unknown to Ficino, as Diès's second chapter of his Essai , "La tradition antique et Proclus," demonstrates.


40

termines whether births will be better or worse."[95] However, in the analysis of proposition 47 near the very end of his commentary, having noted that the hypotenuse and side of an isosceles right triangle cannot both be expressed in rational numbers, Proclus turns to the Pythagoreans' "beautiful" scalene, where indeed the "square on the side subtending the right angle is equal to the squares on the sides containing it," and boldly declares, perhaps echoing Plutarch, "Such is the triangle in the Republic , where sides of three and four contain the right angle and a side of five subtends it."[96] By contrast, as we shall see, Ficino will take up the isosceles triangle, not the exemplary scalene, as the key to Plato's mystery. Characteristically, moreover, he will fail to mention Proclus at all in his De Numero Fatali ,[97] except to say once, at the end of chapter 7, that Plotinus and Proclus had proven "most subtly that numbers exist in the prime being itself as the first distinguishers there both of beings and of ideas."

Indeed, given Ficino's profound, acknowledged, and lasting indebtedness to Plotinus, and given that he had just finished translating and analyzing the Enneads in their entirety—his Plotini Enneades being published in 1492—we might have expected certain Plotinian treatises to be in the forefront of his mind; and notably perhaps 6.6 [34 in the chronological order] entitled "On Numbers," one of the great meditations of Plotinus's maturity. But Plotinus's concerns here are exclusively ontological, and he gives no indication of being influenced by, or interested in, the arithmological tradition as developed

[95] Ed. Gottfried Friedlein (Leipzig, 1873), pp. 8.12 ff., 23.21 ff.; trans. Glenn R. Morrow as Proclus: A Commentary on the First Book of Euclid's Elements (Princeton, 1970), pp. 7, 20.

[96] Ed. Friedlein, pp. 427.25 ff.; trans. Morrow, pp. 339–340. Cf. Schneider, Platonis Opera Graece 3:xxxii–xxxiii (his sole reference to Proclus since he did not know of the Melissa !); Dupuis, Nombre , p. 20; Adam, Republic , p. 267; and Diès, Essai , p. 77.

[97] See my Platonism , pp. 249–255.


41

by the Pythagoreans.[98] For him, as apparently for the later Plato, ordinary quantitative numbers are merely images of the ideal numbers, which, he argues, on the basis of his metaphysical conviction that the One is above Being, are in Intellect but higher than other Ideas. These ideal numbers are thus at the very apex of the intelligible world and serve as the principles of being, as the highest level of Ideas, as the measures of all reality. Indeed, according to Porphyry's Life 14.7–10, Plotinus seems to have dismissed the preoccupations of ordinary mathematicians as irrelevant to the philosopher, though he was well acquainted with Plato's various mathematical concerns and alludes to the account in the Timaeus 39BC and 47A ff. of the origins of man's idea of number in his exposure to the alternation of night and day. Indeed, despite the De Numero Fatali and various disquisitions of his own on the musical proportions, Ficino probably willingly embraced this Plotinian dismissal, sanctioned as it was by such passages in the Republic as 7.529CD where Socrates insists that genuinely philosophical astronomy is concerned with "true" number and figure and not with the visible motions of the heavenly bodies. Be that as it may, the larger underlying issues of the passage in the Republic 8, namely the nature and function of the celestial circuits and their role in the providential plan, and the question of man's freedom of choice in the midst of a sensible reality governed by destiny, are very much Plotinian issues and figure prominently in 3.2–3 [47–48], the late treatise on providence, in 2.3 [52], the even later treatise on astrology, and in 3.1 [3], the early treatise on destiny. Nonetheless, despite his fundamental Plotinianism, one does not sense here the presence, or at least the pressure, of Plotinian texts, except perhaps in his concluding chapter on astrology.[99]

[98] See A. H. Armstrong's comments in the headnote to his translation of the treatise in the seventh and last volume of his Loeb Plotinus (Cambridge, Mass., and London, 1966–1988), pp. 6–8: "he does not seem to have been very much interested in or affected by the Pythagorean or Pythagoreanizing numerologists." Armstrong adduces Janine Bertier's comments to the same effect in her edition of the treatise, along with translation and commentary (Paris, 1980), introd., pp. 9–10. He does, however, draw our attention to Plotinus's discussion of Aristotle's account of ideal numbers in the Metaphysics A, M, and N. We should note that Plotinus had a full knowledge of the subject and recommends its practice; see his Enneads 1.3 [20].5.5–10.

[99] The mention of Plotinus and Proclus at the conclusion of chapter 7 already cited above is Ficino's only allusion in the De Numero Fatali to the problem of the Platonic mathematicals and their status vis-à-vis the Ideas.

We should recall that for the Greeks in general the unit is outside the number series, Aristotle defining number as "a plurality of units" or alternatively as a "limited plural-

ity" (Metaphysics 1039a12, 1053a30 versus 1020a13; see Guthrie, History of Greek Philosophy 5:439n). The Phaedo 101B9–C9 declares that there are Forms of numbers in which individual numbers participate (see Guthrie, History 4:523)

Given the absence of any unequivocal mention of an intermediate class of mathematicals in the dialogues themselves (see Guthrie, History 4:343–345, citing Cherniss), Ficino's primary source for the Platonic status of mathematicals was, ironically, Aristotle, who declares in his Metaphysics 987b14–18 and ff.: "Besides the sensibles and the Forms Plato posits mathematical objects in between, differing from the sensibles in being eternal and unmoved, and from the Forms in that there are many alike, whereas the Form itself is in every case unique." Again at 997b1 he writes of "the Forms and the intermediates, with which they say the mathematical sciences are concerned." For these and other such passages in Aristotle, see Adam, Republic 2:160, and Guthrie, History 4:343, 523.

While mathematicals are nowhere named in the Republic , later interpreters have argued they are part of the upper half of the Divided Line at 509D. While the matter of what Plato himself believed has been the subject of endless controversy among modern scholars, Ficino was in no doubt of their existence, given the Neoplatonic tradition and above all the testimony of Proclus.

The Republic 7.521C–531D deals with the mathematical education of the guardians (i.e., Ficino's magistratus ); see F. M. Cornford, "Mathematics and Dialectic in Republic VI and VII," in Studies in Plato's Metaphysics , ed. R. E. Allen (London, 1965), pp. 61–95.


42

In short, having found no guidance earlier in the Platonic tradition, and having wandered earnestly in the "delightful meadows" of the first twelve treatises of Proclus's Republic Commentary that had come to his attention as late as 1492 and still found nothing, Ficino must have gradually concluded that he would have to attempt an independent explication of the geometric number. For the mathematical treatises of Theon, of Nicomachus, and of Iamblichus, the extant philosophical treatises of his two most revered Platonic authorities, Plotinus and Proclus, the essays even of Plutarch—all had maintained a judicious Pythagorean silence. The sources of Ficino's wider knowledge of astronomy, judicial astrology, and harmonics are of course another matter, but would include Ptolemy, Calcidius, Macrobius, Martianus Capella, Proclus again, Boethius, and a number of medieval figures, along with medieval epitomes and handbooks.

Thus the starting point for him clearly remained: first, the contentious passage in the fifth book of Aristotle's Politics ; and second, what Plato had to say about the cosmological significance of numbers and their proportions in the Timaeus[100] and Epinomis . These texts—

[100] Indeed, as Diès, Essai , p. 20, notes, the Timaeus remained a point of departure for exegesis until the twentieth century: "Toutefois, les exégètes du Nombre platonicien trouveront leur bien dans ces calculs sur la composition de l'âme du monde, et le double quaternaire, pair et impair, 1, 2, 4, 8, 1, 3, 9, 27, continuera, au moins à partir du XVI siècle jusqu'à nos jours (Dupuis, Hultsch, etc.), d'être invoqué pour expliquer les 'accroissements à trois intervalles et quatre termes.'"


43

along of course with the Platonic lemmata of 546A-D[101] —account for the musical and astronomical-astrological cast of the argument throughout Ficino's De Numero Fatali , and for its concern with why a perfectly constituted state must necessarily decline along with all other things after what is a finite term, however vast, however indeterminable it may seem in the darkened glass of our understandings. At stake, as the last chapter testifies, is the status of astrological disposition and influence in the providential order, and thus the problematic relationship between man's divinely ordained freedom and the motion of the stars—the relationship, that is, between transitory human time and what the Timaeus 40C calls the intricate "choric dances" of celestial time.

[101] There were, incidentally, no scholia particularly useful for Ficino here except possibly for the longish gloss on 546B3's "theiôi men genêtôi, " and the diagrams of three "perfect" scalene triangles (with sides of 3–4–5, 9–12–15, and 27–36–45 respectively) keyed to 546C4's "promêkei de, " representing a Proclan explanation of the phrase "at the third augmentation." See William Chase Greene, ed. Scholia Platonica, American Philological Association Monograph 8 (Haverford, Pa., 1938; reprint Chico, Calif., 1981), pp. 256–257; and Boter, Textual Tradition, pp. 345–346.


44

2
Figured Numbers and the Fatal Number

"Magnus ab integro saeclorum nascitur ordo"


In order to understand Ficino's unraveling of Plato's mathematical mystery in his commentary on the Republic 8, we must first familiarize ourselves briefly with aspects of the basic terminology of traditional Pythagorean arithmogeometry, arithmology, and the lore of figured numbers, as Ficino himself had become acquainted with them earlier in his career by way of Theon of Smyrna's Expositio . We must bear in mind that his mathematical explanations and excursions here are oriented towards one particular goal: the interpretation of perhaps the most riddling passage in the Plato canon. Certainly, he never intended his commentary to serve as a counterpart to, or even as a compendium of, the various ancient introductions to mathematics, notably those by Theon himself and by Nicomachus and his commentators. Portions of his own earlier Timaeus Commentary had to a degree already served that purpose, especially with regard to promoting a Platonic understanding of musical proportions and harmonics and of the crucial role they had played in the Creator-Demiurge's structuring of the material world and of the World-Soul and other souls.[1] It is the Timaeus indeed, not Aristotle's Politics , that provides us with our starting point.

From his earliest years as a scholar, the Timaeus up to 53C was fa-

[1] See especially chapters 28–34 (Opera , pp. 1451.2–1460.2).


45

miliar to Ficino in the Latin translation embedded in Calcidius's great commentary;[2] and he had learned to interpret it initially through the Middle Platonic, or possibly Neoplatonic, spectacles of that commentary.[3] Subsequently he mastered the Greek original and then turned to study the other great Timaeus commentary extant from antiquity, and for him the more authoritative of the two because unquestionably and profoundly Neoplatonic, the massive and difficult work by Proclus, though once again he only had access to a manuscript containing the first half.[4] As a consequence, his own Timaeus Commentary seems to have passed through a number of drafts as he became more and more adroit or confident in handling the dialogue's profusion of ideas and images: it is one of his very first Platonic labors and also one of his last, and it incorporates several chronological layers of interpretation.[5]

When Socrates observes in book 8 of the Republic that the geometric number is a "human" and imperfect number, and that it has four terms and three intervals related to each other in certain proportions, to elucidate his meaning seems to require, at least for a Neoplatonist

[2] Milan's Biblioteca Ambrosiana has a MS (S. 14 sup.) containing this commentary on ff. 4–98v with abundant marginalia and bearing the arms of Ficino—two stars on either side of an upright sword—and a note on f. 172r that he had copied out the whole MS during February and March of 1454 (Florentine style) when he was only twenty. See Raymond Klibansky, The Continuity of the Platonic Tradition during the Middle Ages (Munich, 1981), p. 30; Kristeller, Supplementum 1:liv; idem, Iter 1:342; idem, Ficino and His Work , pp. 93–94; and Gentile in Mostra , pp. 7–8 (no. 6).

[3] In the introduction to his edition, Timaeus a Calcidio Translatus (see Chapter 1, n. 2 above), Calcidius's distinguished modern editor J. H. Waszink has argued for the influence on Calcidius (whom he assigns to the first half of the fourth century) of the Timaeus Commentary by Plotinus's leading disciple and biographer, Porphyry (c. 232–305 A.D. ). Stephen Gersh, Middle Platonism and Neoplatonism: The Latin Tradition , 2 vols. (Notre Dame, Ind., 1986), 2:421–492, also argues for the influence of Porphyry and of the Neopythagorean Numenius and assigns Calcidius's activity to the late fourth and early fifth centuries (p. 424n). Dillon, Middle Platonists , pp. 401–408, on the other hand, disputes the presence of anything other than Middle Platonic sources, while admitting that linguistic considerations would suggest the fifth rather than the fourth century for its composition (p. 402). Ficino was obviously not in the position of being able to assess Calcidius in these terms. While he speaks of him as a Platonist and lists his commentary among the Platonic books to be found among the Latins in a letter to Martinus Uranius (alias Prenninger) of June 1489 (Opera , p. 899), he refers to him only twice in his own Timaeus Commentary—in chapters 19 and 42 (Opera , pp. 1446.1, 1463.2)—and only rarely elsewhere. Certainly he never accorded him the stature he accorded Plotinus, Proclus, and the Areopagite.

[4] MS Ricc. gr. 24—this ends at sômasi in the middle of the third book (ed. Diehl, 2:169.4)—see Chapter 1, n. 22 above. For Ficino's debts to the Proclus commentary, see Gentile in Mostra , pp. 109–110 (no. 87), and my "Ficino's Interpretation of Plato's Timaeus ," pp. 422–426, 431–434.

[5] Allen, "Ficino's Interpretation of Plato's Timaeus ," pp. 402–403 and n., with further references.


46

committed to a synoptic view of the canon, recourse to the wellknown argumentation of the Timaeus at 35B ff. and 43D. Here Timaeus deals with the generation of the first two cubes of 8 and 27 by way of the two quaternary sequences 1–2–4–8 and 1–3–9–27, which commentators since antiquity have visualized as a lambda, the eleventh letter in the Greek alphabet. In the process he invites us to examine the proportional relationship between 8 and 27 in terms of two means, 12 and 18,[6] and thereby establishes a set of fundamental proportions or what we now think of as ratios (though Euclid and Nicomachus, for instance, had insisted that "proportion" should be reserved only for a relationship between at least three terms embracing two ratios).[7] The Pythagoreans and the Platonists found it significant

[6] At 31B–32B Timaeus had noted that, while square numbers such as 4 and 9 require only one geometric mean (in this case 6), cube numbers require two means; cf. Ficino's Timaeus Commentary 19 (Opera , p. 1446.1), and Euclid, Elements 8, props. 11 and 12. With these means, the lambda, which signifies 30, is transformed, like the tetraktys, into a triangle, into a delta signifying the all-important 4! Even so, 6 remains its key in that the products of the three descending steps as it were of the lambda—that is, of 2x3, of 4x6x9, and of 8x12x18x27—are all powers of 6, 216 being its cube, and 46,656 being the square of that cube (or 6 x6 or 6 x6 x6 or 6 ).

[7] Euclid, Elements 5, defs. 3–5, 8 (and in general defs. 1–18), and 7, def. 20; Nicomachus, Introductio 2.21.2–3, 2.24; cf. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics 5.3.1131a31 ff. See Michel, De Pythagore , pp. 366–369, and Fowler, Mathematics of Plato's Academy , pp. 16–21. In his Expositio Theon takes logos to mean "the relationship of proportion or ratio" or the "ratio of proportion" (2.18,19), though he also speaks of the proportion as defining "the relationship of ratios with each other" (2.21); Adrastus, he says, had claimed that the geometric mean alone is a "true proportion" (2.50) (ed. Hiller, pp. 72.24–74.7, 74.12–14, 106.14–20).

Ficino's access to and knowledge of Euclid has yet to be investigated. The Elements were rendered into Latin from Arabic translations by Adelard of Bath (fl. 1116–1142), apparently in three distinct versions, by Hermann of Carinthia (fl. c. 1140–1150), and by Gerard of Cremona (c. 1114–1187); and directly from the Greek by an anonymous twelfth-century Sicilian scholar enjoying the patronage perhaps of the Admiral Eugenius, Emir of Palermo (1130–1203). However, the standard medieval if thoroughly "scholasticized" redaction was done by Campanus of Novara in 1255–1259 (and eventually published in Venice in 1482, and again in 1486 and 1491). A "free reworking" of earlier translations from the Arabic, including Adelard's, it included books 14 and 15 and sought to elucidate the axiomatic structure of the Elements by emphasizing arithmetical rather than geometrical proof. It was revised and reissued by Luca Pacioli (Paciuolo) in 1509 in response to the new humanist version by Bartolomeo Zamberti published in 1505; and the two competing versions were then issued in 1516 by Faber Stapulensis in a composite volume. The editio princeps of the Greek text by Simon Grynaeus did not appear until 1533. Earlier, the distinguished mathematician and astronomer Regiomontanus (1436–1476) had set about revising the Campanus version in the 1470s, though this revision has been lost since 1625; however, a copy of Adelard's Latin Euclid that belonged to him does survive, dating from 1459 and containing annotations up to the seventh book. For further references, see Heath's introduction to his translation of the Elements (1:92–101); Paul Lawrence Rose, The Italian Renais-

sance of Mathematics (Geneva, 1975), pp. 50–52, 77–79, 81, 93, 106, and 144; and H. L. L. Busard, The First Latin Translation of Euclid's "Elements" Commonly Ascribed to Adelard of Bath (Books I-VIII and Books X.36-XV.2), Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies: Studies and Texts, 64 (Toronto, 1983), pp. 2–15 (Busard, incidentally, has now edited all the pre-Campanus Latin versions).

We might note that in his entire works Ficino never alludes to the Elements , and that the references to "Euclides" in his Opera , pp. 764 and 1008, are to Euclid of Megara, the philosopher who lived c. 400 B.C. However, from the Middle Ages to the end of the sixteenth century, translators, editors, and commentators frequently confused the two Euclids (though Lascaris, for one, had correctly distinguished them); see Heath, Elements 1:3–4. Ficino too may therefore have thought them one and the same.


47

that the proportions between 27 and 18, 18 and 12, and 12 and 8 are all in the same ratio of 3:2.[8] But between the two cubes 27 and 8 exist the two squares 16 and 9, with 12 mediating between them by way again of the same ratio, this time of 4:3.

It was precisely these two ratios of 3:2 and 4:3 that Ficino was to bring to bear on his elucidation of the crux in the Republic , more particularly since they appear to be underscored by the important testimony of Aristotle's Politics at 5.12.8. For here Aristotle argues that Plato had established "the origin of change" in a hitherto perfect state in a number with a "root" in the ratio of 4:3, and that this root "when joined to the five gives two harmonies." By "two harmonies," Aristotle concludes, Plato had meant "when the number of this diagram—or [in Acciaiuoli's and Ficino's rendering] the description of this figure—becomes solid."[9] The "fatal geometric" number will therefore be a "solid," and specifically a cube, and the clue to its discovery will lie in the understanding of number sequences, of square and cube numbers, and of the nature of certain primary proportions. We therefore need to be acquainted with the basic categories, as Ficino understood them, of what the Pythagorean tradition had presented as figured or figural numbers.

I. We should begin with Ficino's working assumptions about, and definitions of, the kinds or classes of numbers. These will be largely familiar to those scholars already acquainted with the ancient Pythagorean mathematical tradition as fully described by Paul-Henri Michel, for instance, in the monumental study already cited.[10] However, this

[8] Cf. Ficino's Timaeus Commentary 19 (Opera , p. 1446.1).

[9] "'quorum sexquitertia radix coniuncta quinario duas exhibet harmonias,' dicens videlicet quando numeri huius descriptio fiat solida"—as rendered by Ficino towards the end of his De Numero Fatali 12 (see Chapter 1, n. 19 above). For "diagram" (diagramma ), see n. 12 to Text 2, p. 166 below.

[10] De Pythagore , esp. part 2, chapters 1 and 2.


48

Pythagorean dimension of Ficino's work and intellectual background has remained up till now entirely unexplored, perhaps even unsuspected, by scholars of Renaissance Platonism; and the terrain as a whole is rather forbidding. In the following analysis the references in parentheses are to the chapter and line numberings of my edition of the text (Text 3 in Part Two below).

A. Odd numbers Ficino thinks of as male, as indivisible, and as incorporeal, since they derive "from their own root or seed" (6.63–64), an assumption that necessarily follows given the Neoplatonic status of the 1 as their "mean and center" (8.38–39). They have "greater kinship with oneness"; and they "abound" with it, beginning with, ending in, and converting to it (8.36–39). The even numbers by contrast are female, divisible, and corporeal, the 2 being the first "fall" from the 1 and thus the first instance of division and diversity. Ficino refers to the 2 as being like indeterminate matter, citing Archytas as supposing the 1 is the Idea of the odd numbers while the 2 is the Idea of the even (8.19–22).[11]

Odd numbers possess the one as "the bond" or "hinge" of themselves, and exist about the 1 as their center; while even numbers once divided are "torn apart" and none of their parts survive, the odd numbers once divided continue to exist with the 1 in their parts as the "indivisible link" (8.39–43). Hence they seem to be "unfolded" rather than "divided." Or, to use a traditional emanative metaphor, while the even numbers flow in the initial procession out from the 1, the odd numbers are at the second stage—they turn back towards the 1, the 1 which is "like the world's maker" in that it creates "order" for them and is their "measure" and "principle" (8.3–19, 46–47, 60–64).

The first number as such is the 3, the 2 being not so much a number as the "first fall from the one," "the first "multitude" (6.46–47; 8.79–80). This situation Ficino declares "is like the mystery of the Christian Trinity" (8.22–23). The "fate" of the first number 3 is thus

[11] Cf. Euclid, Elements 7, defs. 6–11; Aristotle, Metaphysics 986a22 ff., with the Pythagorean table of ten opposites—limited and unlimited, odd and even, one and many, right and left, male and female, rest and motion, straight and crooked, light and darkness, good and bad, square and oblong; idem, Physics 203a10: "The Pythagoreans identify the unlimited with the even"; and Iamblichus, De Vita Pythagorica 28.156: the right is the origin of the odd numbers and is divine, the left is the symbol of the divisible even numbers.

See Michel, De Pythagore , p. 332: "l'arithmologie des Pythagoriciens accorde à l'impair une sorte d'avantage sur le pair"; also Dillon, Middle Platonists , pp. 3–5.


49

paradigmatic of the "fates" of all numbers, 3 of course being the number of the Fates themselves (15.10–11).[12] Three is as it were at the third perfective stage in the emanative cycle, the return to the 1 (6.77–79) where it "abounds" in it as in "its head and bond" (9.5–6). Because of this abundance or "copiousness," the 3 is called masculine.

If the male odd numbers abound, the female even numbers by contrast suffer from "dearth," "partition," and "fall" (6.80–81). Ficino acknowledges that such a view runs counter to the "human and moral praise" we usually extend to the even numbers because they can be equally and therefore justly distributed (if we are thinking, that is, of enacting justice among equals). But, he argues, "the more sacred and divine praise" is directed towards the odd numbers such as 3, 7, and 9; for they "comprehend" the even and are "hinged" upon the 1 as their "mean," "center," and "god," the 1 which is the source of equal distribution and "the principle of the world's order" (6.82–87, 95–97). Clearly, Christian trinitarian assumptions are reinforced by such definitions.

Despite his acceptance of 3 as the first number proper, there are times when Ficino thinks of 2 and indeed of 1 also as numbers; for all numbers look to the 1 as their source according to the ancient tag that they are 1 multiplied.[13] Strictly speaking, 1 is both odd and even, but the Pythagoreans thought of it more as odd on the grounds that, while evens are divided and destroyed and thus torn apart from the 1, the odds are "unfolded" from it and retain it as their center (8.39–43). The 1 as odd is thus the ultimate principle of identity and likeness and as such resembles God.

"Simple" or uncompounded numbers are those which Ficino thinks of as "consisting of" and "being measured by" the 1 alone, such as 3, 5, 7, 11, 13, 17, and so on. They are the prime numbers, and Ficino, following the Euclidean tradition, describes them as the "prime unequals."[14] "Compound" numbers therefore are those which are products of factors other than 1, as 6 is the product of 3x2.[15] Compounds that are odd and therefore compounded by factors that

[12] As in Plato's Republic 10.617C ff. (with Ficino's epitome, Opera , p. 1434).

[13] Theon, Expositio 1.7 (ed. Hiller, p. 24.23): "as for the 1, it is not a number, but the principle of number." See Michel, De Pythagore , p. 332. Ficino usually thinks of 2 not 4, however, as the first even number (but cf. 3.40–42).

[14] Two is not considered as belonging to this category; cf. Theon, Expositio 1.6 (ed. Hiller, pp. 23.6–24.8). See Michel, De Pythagore , p. 330.

[15] Theon, Expositio 1.7 (ed. Hiller, p. 24.16–23). See Michel, De Pythagore , p. 331.


50

are both odd—15 for instance as the product of 5x3—are said to be "oddly odd"; whereas compounds that are even are said to be either "oddly even" if just one of the factors is even—10 for instance as the product of 5x2—or "evenly even" if both of the factors are even—8 for instance as the product of 4x2.[16] Various individual numbers clearly fall into more than one class; 12, for instance, we can think of as the product either of 6x2 or of 4x3, and therefore as either "evenly even" or "oddly even." These definitions are crucial, given Ficino's wrestling with the lemma at 546C3 "isên isakis " ("aequalem aequa-liter").

B. There are three important related categories of numbers that the Pythagorean tradition characterized as either "perfect," or "abundant," or "deficient."[17]

First is the category of truly perfect numbers. Though 10 is thought by the Pythagoreans to be a perfect number and 1 is perfect in power,[18] a truly perfect number is exceedingly rare, since it is identical with the sum of its own factors, its aliquot partes (4.18–19).[19] Six is the first of such numbers, being the sum of 3+2+1; 28 is the second, being the sum of 14+7+4+2+1; 496 is the third and 8128 the fourth (17.29–31). There are still higher perfect numbers, but Ficino never mentions them.[20] He perceives a mystical significance in the fact that the last digits of these first four perfect numbers alternate be-

[16] See Michel, De Pythagore , pp. 333–334—citing Euclid, Elements 7, defs. 8–11 [10]: "evenly even" (8), "evenly odd" (9), "oddly even" (10), "oddly odd" (11)—and p. 336—citing Theon, Expositio 1.8–10 (i.e., ed. Hiller, pp. 25.5–26.13). In using "oddly odd" as a term for compound odd numbers Ficino seems to be following Euclid rather than Theon, who reserves the term for the prime odd numbers—see Expositio 1.6 (ed. Hiller, p. 23.14, 16, 21). However, he seems to be ignoring Euclid's, or an interpolator's, finespun distinction between "evenly odd" and "oddly even," a distinction also noted by Theon in 1.9 and 1.10. Heiberg and Heath both in fact reject def. 10 as the work of an interpolator; see Heath's note on def. 9 in his translation of the Elements (2:282–284).

[17] See Michel, De Pythagore , pp. 342–346.

[18] Theon, Expositio 2.39–40 (ed. Hiller, pp. 99.17–20, 99.24–100.8); Nicomachus, Introductio 1.16.8–10 (on one). For the Pythagoreans' praise of 10's perfection, see Aristotle, Metaphysics 1.5.986a9–11.

[19] Cf. Euclid, Elements 7, def. 22; 9, prop. 36; Theon, Expositio 1.32 (ed. Hiller, pp. 45.9–46.3); and Nicomachus, Introductio 1.16; also Plutarch, De Animae Procreatione 13 (Moralia 1018C). See Michel, De Pythagore , pp. 342–346.

[20] Iamblichus, In Nicomachi Arith. Introd. 33.20–23 (ed. Pistelli), alludes to the possibility of the fifth perfect number, that is, 33,550,336. See Heath's table of the first ten perfect numbers, Greek Mathematics 1:74–75.


51

tween 6 and 8 in what he calls "a marvelous vicissitude";[21] and he also finds it significant that only one such number occurs below 10, one again between 10 and a 100, one between a 100 and a 1000, and one between a 1000 and 10,000 (17.31–35, 45–47).[22] Six is doubly perfect for Ficino because it has the perfect ratio of 2:1 within itself in that 6 equals 4+2, and 4:2 is the double ratio of 2:1 (4.23–26). The perfect numbers "contain the circuit itself of divine generation"—"as rare as is the perfection, so rare is the divine progeny that proceeds" (17.42–43, 47–48).

Most numbers, however, are "deficient," that is, their factors add up to a sum less than themselves: for instance, 8, the first of such numbers, has as its factors 4, 2 and 1, but they only add up to 7 (4.28–30).

Finally, an "abundant" or "increasing" number is one where the sum of its factors exceeds itself. Twelve is the first of such numbers, the sum of its factors of 6, 4, 3, 2, and 1 being 16 (4.32–35). Twelve is also abundant because it is the product of the "twinning" of 6, the perfect number (3.57–58).23

C. Still another category interests Ficino, that of the "circular" numbers, numbers whose powers happen to end in the same digit. Besides being the first of the perfect numbers, 6 is also an example of a circular number in that both its square of 36 and its cube of 216 also end in 6. Another example of such a number is 5 with its square of 25 and its cube of 125. However, 4 has its circularity "intercepted in the plane" of 16 even though its cube of 64 ends in 4; it is thus an example of a "lesser" circular number (17.8–15).[24]

[21] This alternation does not pertain for higher perfect numbers, though Ficino might have supposed it did following Nicomachus, Introductio 1.16.3,7 and Boethius, De Institutione Arithmetica 1.20.

[22] Nicomachus, Introductio 1.16.3, mentions this distribution whereas Theon only mentions 6 and 28. See Robbins in D'Ooge, Nicomachus , p. 52, who notes it was incorrect of Nicomachus to imply both that a perfect number can be found in each order of the powers of 10 and that all such numbers alternately end in 6 and 8.

[23] Theon, Expositio 1.32 (ed. Hiller, p. 46.4–14), and Nicomachus, Introductio 1.14,15, not Euclid, provided Ficino with the definition of both abundant and deficient numbers.

There is a fourth category, incidentally, that Ficino never alludes to here, namely of "friendly numbers"—where one of two numbers is equal to the sum of the aliquot parts of the other. Iamblichus, In Nicomachi Arith. Introd. 35.3–5 (ed. Pistelli), attributed their invention to Pythagoras, and the only such numbers known to antiquity seem to have been 220 and 284; magical powers were attributed to both. See Michel, De Pythagore , pp. 343, 346–348.

[24] For circular numbers, see Theon, Expositio 1.24 (ed. Hiller, pp. 38.16–39.9);

also the Theologumena 36.17 (ed. de Falco), and Nicomachus, Introductio 2.17.7. Cf. Ficino's Timaeus Commentary 17 (Opera , pp. 1444.4–1445): "etsi superiores numeros ratione ortus sui alios quadratos alios oblongos nominant, tamen ratione casus atque finis nuncupant circulares." Thus 5 and 6 are the "prime roots" of the circulars and thus the "circular body of the world" is divided into five or six elements; cf. ibid. 20 (Opera , p. 1446.2), which states that 5 and 6 "are in accord with the circular shape of the world" ("circulari mundi figurae congruere").


52

D. A "spousal" or "nuptial" number is the product of two adjacent numbers: for instance, 6 is the product of 2x3 and 12 of 3x4. Indeed, 6 is the first "spousal" number because it is the product of the first odd (and therefore male) number multiplying the first even (and therefore female) number—and was so denominated by the Pythagoreans. Ficino specifically says that 12 is the second "spousal" as the product of 3x4; and presumably, 20 would be the third spousal as 4x5, 30 the fourth as 5x6, 42 the fifth as 6x7, and so on. Multiples of factors differing by more than 1 cannot be called spousal (4.41–45).

Interestingly, the heading of Ficino's expositio in all the texts speaks of "the nuptial number" whereas the heading of his commentary proper speaks of "the fatal number." Antiquity had often identified the two numbers on the grounds that Plato's fatal number must be especially regarded by the magistrates when they set about orchestrating public mass marriages.[25] But Ficino obviously intended us to keep the idea of a nuptial number quite distinct from that of a fatal number, since his two proposed fatal numbers are not products of adjacent male and female numbers, but rather numbers with cube roots, though admittedly one of these roots is indeed a spousal number. In short, from Ficino's perspective Plato was concerned in the Republic with at least three kinds of mystical numbers: with the fatal numbers that signal the onset of a perfect constitution's decline; with the nuptial numbers that signal the best opportunities for marriage and begetting in a state that wants to resist a decline before its fatal time; and with the truly perfect numbers that betoken and preside over the divine births Plato writes of at 546B3.

II. Let us now turn to various conceptions of numbers as products. Of these there are three kinds: linear, plane, and solid and the terms can be used in the Pythagorean tradition of sums as well as of products.[26]

[25] See Chapter 1, n. 4 above. Ficino's most likely sources were Iamblichus, In Nicomachi Arith. Introd. 82.17–24 (ed. Pistelli), and Plutarch, De Iside 56 (Moralia 373F).

[26] Cf. Timaeus 31C ff. and Ficino's Timaeus Commentary 19 (Opera , pp.

(footnote continued on the next page)


53

A. All numbers when seen as the products of 1 or that have no factor other than 1 are called "linear." But when numbers are the products of two numbers other than 1, then such composites are called "plane," and this is so whether they are the products of the same factor multiplying itself (in which case the plane will be a square) or of one factor multiplying another. Thus 4 as 2x2, 6 as 3x2, 8 as 4x2, 9 as 3x3, 10 as 5x2, and 12 as both 3x4 and 6x2 are all planes. Obviously, planes multiplying either linear numbers or other planes will always produce further planes as the case of 12 above illustrates: and the multiplication of two planes that are squares, for instance, 4 and 9, will always produce another square, in this case 36 (11.8–10).[27] Equally obviously, as both 12 and 36 demonstrate, a number can be a plane in different ways: 12 is either 6x2 or 3x4; 36 is either 6x6 or 9x4 or 12x3 or 18x2.

"Solid" numbers are the products of three factors greater than 1, whether of the same factor multiplying itself twice (in which case the solid is a cube), or of a factor multiplying itself and another factor, or of three different factors multiplying each other.[28] Again Ficino and the Pythagorean tradition were particularly interested in "solid" products that were cubes. Thus 8, 27, 64, and 125 are the cubic solids of 2, 3, 4, and 5 respectively. Obviously, cubes multiplying cubes will always produce further cubes: for instance, the two prime cubes 8 and 27 multiplied together produce 216, the cube of 6 (11.14–15). Solid numbers are known Platonically as "of the three" (5.44–45).[29]

Clearly, some numbers that are products can be viewed as linear, or as plane, or as solid: 8, for instance, can be seen as 8x1 or as 2x4 or as 2x2x2. But their solidity will be their most characteristic or important mode.[30] Moreover, we should constantly bear in mind that both plane and solid numbers seen as products can also be viewed as sums, and this is particularly important if they are sums in one of the three primary series I shall outline later.

B. Among plane and solid numbers there are three kinds of products; and these Ficino designates, following Plato's Theaetetus 147E–148B and Theon's Expositio , as "equilateral" (Theon's "equally equal"),

(footnote continued from the previous page)

[1445] 3–1446): "Triplices esse numeros apud Pythagoricos alibi declaravimus, lineares, planos, solidos." See Michel, De Pythagore , pp. 298–299.

[27] Euclid, Elements 7, defs. 16 (plane), 18 (square); and 9, prop. 1.

[28] Euclid, Elements 7, defs. 17 (solid), 19 (cube); and 9, props. 3–7.

[29] Because of Aristotle's gloss on 546C6? See n. 9 above.

[30] See Michel, De Pythagore , p. 298.


54

"unequilateral" or "oblong" (Theon's "unequally unequal"), and "diagonal."31

i. An "equilateral" is the product of any number multiplying itself—either once to produce its square or twice to produce its cube. Uniquely as always, the 1 too is an equilateral insofar as it is the square and the cube of itself (6.30–32; 8.51–55). All other equilaterals resemble it in their "equality and straightness" since it is their "seed" (8.48–53). Accordingly, the first series or succession of equilaterals as products is the regular succession of square numbers: [1], 4, 9, 16, 25, 36, 49, 64, 81, 100, and so on.[32] In a way these equilaterals are like God, muses Ficino, in that God "acting with Himself [multiplying Himself as it were] procreates others" (8.70). But, he continues in an extension of the analogy, cube numbers are like God when He uses the prime being as His means.[33] Thus if we think of God as 2, then His first created being will be 2x2, and all subsequent beings He creates directly will be 2x2x2. But if we think of God using the prime being as His means to create them, then we must replace 2x2x2 with 2x4, 4 (as 2x2) being the prime being whom God multiplies. Similarly 27 can be viewed either as 3x3x3 or as 3x9 (8.64–72). It is difficult to gauge the force of these distinctions for Ficino.

An equilateral number of peculiar importance is the "universal" number 100 (as 102 ) and the multiples that immediately "teem" from it and from 10 its root: 1000 (as 103 ), 10,000 (as 1002 ) and 1,000,000 (as 1003 ) (3.75–77).

[31] Expositio 1.11–12 ("un/equilateral"), 31 ("diagonal") (ed. Hiller, pp. 26.14,18–19; 42.10–44.8). See below.

[32] See Michel, De Pythagore , pp. 304–305.

[33] Ficino is thinking here Neoplatonically. He is equating God with the first hypostasis, the One, and the prime being with Mind, the second hypostasis. From Mind proceeds Soul, the third hypostasis, and thence Quality and the realm of Body. In Christian terms the realm of Mind can be equated, in part at least, with the angels generically conceived as Angel or as seraphim, the highest of the angels. Hence Ficino is suggesting that we can think of God either as the immediate Creator of everything in the universe or as the Creator by way of the angels, who themselves created, or assisted Him in the creation of, the lower realms. However, insofar as the Neoplatonic hypostasis Mind also suggests God in His immanence (God in His transcendence being identified with the first hypostasis, the One), then we must think of the prime being as signifying the Son. It is not clear what Ficino intends.

For the problems besetting the attempt to accommodate Ficinian metaphysics with trinitarian theology, see my "The Absent Angel in Ficino's Philosophy," Journal of the History of Ideas 36 (1975), 219–240, and "Marsilio Ficino on Plato, the Neoplatonists and the Christian Doctrine of the Trinity," Renaissance Quarterly 37 (1984), 555–584, with further references.


55

ii. An "unequilateral" plane, on the other hand, is the product of two different numbers, and an unequilateral solid of three. Unequilateral planes are in turn subdivided into "long" (heteromêkês ) and "oblong" (promêkês ), though, strictly speaking, the "long" are a special class within the general class of "oblong."[34]

An unequilateral is "long" when it is the product of two numbers differing only by one[35] —differing by 1 being a privileged difference given the unique status of the 1. For instance, 6 is the product of 3x2, 12 of 3x4; or, in the case of solids, 12 is the product of 2x2x3, 18 of 2x3x3. The "long" series is thus [2], 6, 12, 20, 30, 42, 56, 72, 90, 110, 132, 156, 182, 210, 240, and so on. These unequilaterals also constitute from another perspective the sequence of spousal numbers, that is, of 1x2, 2x3, 3x4, 4x5, and so on.

An unequilateral is "oblong," however, when it is the product of numbers differing by more than one, as 15 is the product of 3x5 or 24 of 12x2 or 8x3 or 6x4 (6.18–20). Here the possibilities are endless and of little interest to the Pythagorean tradition. Of course, with the possible exception of 6, which is uniquely long (except as 6x1), all unequilateral long products can also appear as oblong: for example, 12 is both 3x4 (long) and 6x2 (oblong), 20 is 4x5 (long) but also 10x2 (oblong).[36]

An equilateral multiplying another equilateral produces an equilateral: for instance, 4x9=36 [22 x32 =62 ], 16x25=400 [42 x52 =202 ]. But a long unequilateral must multiply an adjacent long unequilateral to produce another long unequilateral: for instance, 6x12=72 [(2x3)x (3x4)=8x9]. An oblong unequilateral multiplying another oblong, or an equilateral multiplying an unequilateral of either kind, both produce an oblong: for instance, 8x15=120 [(2x4)x(3x5)=10x12], 4x6= 24 [(2x2)x(2x3)=4x6], 4x15=60 [(2x2)x(3x5)=6x10]. But a long multiplying an oblong can sometimes produce a long, for instance, 6x15=90 [(2x3)x(3x5)=9x10], or even an equilateral (if the long is itself one factor in the oblong and the other factor is an equilateral), for

[34] Theon, Expositio 1.17 (ed. Hiller, p. 30.12–18), had insisted on this more restrictive meaning for "long." Again cf. Plato, Theaetetus 147E ff., and Nicomachus, Introductio 2.17.1, 2.18.2. See Michel, De Pythagore , pp. 311–321 (pp. 318–319 deal with the various senses of "long"—heteromêkês ).

[35] Theon, Expositio 1.13 (ed. Hiller, p. 26.21–22)—a definition of heteromêkês .

[36] Ibid. 1.17 (ed. Hiller, pp. 30.8–31.8)—a definition of promêkês . Cf. Ficino, Timaeus Commentary 19 (Opera , pp. 1445.4–1446), "Dicimus et oblongos qui ex ductu numeri admodum minoris in numerum longe maiorem conficiuntur, qualis est denarius."


56

instance, 12x108=1296 [(3x4)x(3x4x32 )=362 ]. The multiplication of a cube by an unequilateral never produces another cube, but a cube multiplying a cube always produces another cube, for instance, 8x6=48 and 8x15=120, but 8x27=216 [63 ].37

iii. Finally, there is a category of diagonal (or "diametral") products which Ficino doubtless derived principally from Theon's Expositio 1.31 and which involve the problem of certain irrational numbers and their status.[38] The products are described in chapter 5 as those which are alternatively greater or less by one than double the squares of the sides in a particular sequence of geometric squares. As described by Theon, we obtain the sequence of the squares by adding the value of the diagonal to the side while adding the value of twice the side to the diagonal. For instance, if we start with a side of 2 and a diagonal of 3, then the next such square will have a side of 5 [3+2] and a diagonal of 7 [3+(2x2)], the next a side of 12 [5+7] and a diagonal of 17 [7+ (2x5)], the next a side of 29 [12+17] and a diagonal of 41 [17+ (2x12)], and so forth. The diagonals will be 3, 7, 17, 41, 99, and so on; and each when squared—9, 49, 289, 1681, 9801—will equal double the squares of the sides provided we give or take 1 in alternation. That is, they will equal 8 (as 2x22 ) plus 1, 50 (as 2x52 ) minus 1, 288 (as 2x122 ) plus 1, 1682 (as 2x292 ) minus 1, 9800 (as 2x702 ) plus

[37] Cf. Nicomachus, Introductio 2.24.10,11 (with a specific reference to the Republic 's passage on the number "they call the marriage number").

[38] For the irrational or incommensurable numbers, Ficino would have turned most obviously, apart from Theon, to Plato's Theaetetus 147D–148B, Hippias Major 301D–303C, Laws 7.817E–820B, Parmenides 140B–D, Epinomis 976A–977B, 990C–991A, and, of course, Republic 8.546BD; to Aristotle's Prior Analytics 1.41a23–30, 46b26–37, 50a37–38, 65b16–21, and other texts; and also to Euclid's Elements 2, propositions 9 and 10, and Elements 10, passim. Because, we recall, he had access only to a manuscript containing the first twelve treatises, Ficino cannot have been influenced here by the analyses in the thirteenth treatise of Proclus's Republic Commentary (ed. Kroll, 2:24.16–29.4—see the note by Hultsch on pp. 393–400; trans. Festugière, 2:130–135).

In general see Michel, De Pythagore , part 2, chapter 2 passim, esp. pp. 427–430 (on Theon), 433–441 (on Euclid's two propositions in his second book and on Proclus), 441–455 (on Euclid's tenth book), and 500–511 (on three of the Platonic texts). See also Charles Mugler, Platon et la recherche mathématique de son époque (Strasbourg, 1948), pp. 191–249 (especially pp. 226–236 on the problem of the rational and irrational diagonal); and Fowler, Mathematics of Plato's Academy , pp. 166–192 (on Euclid's tenth book), 192–194 (an appendix on the use of the terms alogos and (ar )rhêtos in Plato, Aristotle, and the pre-Socratics), and 294–308 (on the discovery and role of the phenomenon of incommensurability, with a list on pp. 294–302 of the source material in Democritus, Plato, Aristotle, and so on).


57

1, and so forth. Or, put another way, the square constructed on the diagonal will always be now smaller by 1, now greater by 1, than double the square constructed on the side.[39]

Since this plus-or-minus-one alternation is perfectly regular, from the Pythagorean-Ficinian viewpoint, adaequatio or compensatio emerges in the long run; that is, the "power" of the diagonal as a genus, as distinct from the powers of individual diagonals, maintains a ratio to the "power" of the side of 2:1. Incidentally, the successive values of the accompanying sides—2, 5, 12, 29, 70, and so on—constitute the "lateral" numbers.

Diagonal numbers are defined Platonically as "of the 5" because in the very first instance of the series the side is 2 and the diagonal 3, and the sum of 2+3 is 5 (hence the primacy of the harmony diapente) (5.43–44). For, with the alternating plus-or-minus-1 rule, a side of 2 produces a diagonal of 3 in that (2x22 )+1=32 , a side of 5 produces a diagonal of 7 in that (2x52 )-1=72 , a side of 12 produces a diagonal of 17 in that (2x122 )+1=172 , and so on. With all these diagonal and lateral powers the 1 is called the "equalizer" (5.37–38). We might note that if the sides are even then 1 has to be added to them, but if odd then subtracted from them.

The diagonal numbers were already known to Plato, for in the celebrated passage in the Republic which is our primary concern here he gives 7 as the "rational diagonal" (diametros rhêtos ) of a square with the side of 5. The issue turns on the Pythagorean-Platonic distinction between a rational and an irrational root. While 9 and 49 for instance have rational roots of 3 and 7 respectively, 8 and 50 by contrast have irrational roots of 2.8284271 . . . and 7.0710678 . . . respectively. Nevertheless, 8 and 50 can be said to have rational roots, in the Pythagorean sense, of 3 and 7 in that 9 and 49 are their proximate powers, the nearest squares (equilaterals) to them. Thus 8 and 50 can be said to have both irrational and rational roots, the latter being primary. Accordingly, Ficino followed Theon and what he took to be the Pythagorean-Platonic tradition in postulating both rational and irrational roots for the product of twice the square of the side and then

[39] Cf. Theon, Expositio 1.31 (ed. Hiller, p. 44.14–17): "The square constructed on the diagonal will be now smaller now greater by one than double the square constructed on the side in such a way that these diagonals and sides will always be rational [that is, whole numbers]." See Michel, De Pythagore , p. 428. Put algebraically the problem is to find a series of positive, integral solutions for the equation y[2] = 2x[2] &x1771 where y = the diagonal (diameter) and x = the side.


58

assigning primacy to the rational root. In this way he could arrive at a rational value for the diagonal and hence resolve to his own satisfaction part at least of the infamous crux at 546C4–5, "with individual comparable diagonals requiring one, but those which are not comparable requiring two," comparabilis being his rendering of Plato's rhêtos (rational),[40] in that an expressible ratio derives from a comparability between the power of a diagonal and that of the side.

C. Some products, finally, are "similar," others "dissimilar."[41] The similar are those that the Greeks had traditionally defined as the products of two proportional factors. While equilaterals are always similar (whether as squares or cubes), unequilaterals are similar only when their "sides" or factors are proportional; for example, 6 is similar to 24 in that, as 3x2 and 6x4 respectively, both contain the ratio of 3:2; again 18 and 8 are similar in that, as 6x3 and 4x2 respectively, both contain the ratio of 2:1.[42] All other unequilateral products are dissimilar; for example, 18 and 24 are dissimilar in that, as 6x3 and 6x4 (or 12x2) respectively, they do not share the same ratio (4.46–55).

III. Let us now turn to the figural or geometrical importance that Ficino associates, like the ancients before him, with certain fundamental number series we generate not by multiplication but by addition; that is, to numbers viewed as sums and not as products.[43] This tradition is now largely unfamiliar to us but once held an esteemed place for the Pythagoreans, who were accustomed to conceptualizing sums as extensions in space. The chief authorities for Ficino would have been, as we have seen, the treatise of Theon, and perhaps that of Nicomachus and of his commentators, all of them Neopythagorean works that were probably preserving or amplifying a tradition concerning figured sums and summing stemming from earlier, perhaps even from primitive, Pythagoreanism. Clearly, Ficino was aware from

[40] See n. 17 to Text 2, p. 167 below.

[41] Ficino renders Plato's phrase at 546B6–7, "of those that make like and make unlike"—homoiountôn te kai anomoiountôn , as similantium et dissimilantium , but he interprets it to mean simply "like" and "unlike." See n. 7 to Text 2, p. 165 below.

[42] Cf. Euclid, Elements 7, def. 21, and Theon, Expositio 1.22 (ed. Hiller, pp. 36.12–37.6). See also Michel, De Pythagore , pp. 321–322 on Euclid, Elements 9, prop. 1—the remarkable proposition that the product of two such similar plane numbers is a square number: 6x24=144 (i.e., 12 ); also pp. 341 and 507.

[43] See Michel, De Pythagore , p. 297: "dans l'ancienne arithmo-géométrie—et chez les auteurs qui en conservent la tradition—la préférence est accordée aux nombressommes."


59

the onset of his career that an understanding of such figured sums was a key to the secrets of Platonic mathematics, and this must have been the principal reason behind his decision to work through Theon's Expositio and Iamblichus's Pythagorean treatises. We should note that he was only concerned with figured sums; for such unfigured sums or random additions as 7+2+11 had as little interest for him, and for the Pythagorean-Platonic tradition he was rediscovering, as random products.[44]

Leaving aside the special case of linear numbers seen simply as the sums of ones (or as the products of nx1),[45] let us concentrate on three kinds of "plane" sums. Ficino refers to these likewise as equilateral or unequilateral, or as triangular, and he concentrates on the three paradigmatic series, those resulting from: a) the summing of the regular sequence of odd numbers; b) the summing of the regular sequence of even numbers; and c) the summing of the regular sequence of both odd and even numbers. From his reading of Theon, he was certainly aware of other derivative arithmetic series, those resulting, for instance, from summing by 3's, 4's, 5's, 6's, and so forth.46

A. The "equilateral" series of numbers viewed as sums is the result of adding or "composing" the odd numbers in their regular sequence, starting with 1: 1, 1+3=4, 4+5=9, 9+7=16, 16+9=25, 25+11=36, and so on (6.30–40).[47] Ficino finds it important that the successive sums alternate between odd and even numbers and that the series begins with the addition of 1 and 3. He thinks of 1 as "the leader of the odd and of the equilateral numbers," because it is also, mysteriously and uniquely, the square and the cube of itself (6.40–41, 47–49; 9.31–33). Ficino treats of this addition series first precisely because it generates a category of especial interest to the Pythagorean tradition, and to himself in his analysis of the Plato passage, the category of sums that are also, from another perspective, square products or, to put it another way, that have rational roots. For the successive equilateral sums—1,

[44] Ibid., p. 299.

[45] And so defined by Theon, Expositio 1.6 (ed. Hiller, p. 23.11–14): "arithmoi grammikoi ."

[46] Theon, Expositio 1.26–27 (ed. Hiller, pp. 39.14–41.2).

[47] Cf. Theon, Expositio 1.15 (ed. Hiller, p. 28.3–15), and Nicomachus, Introductio 2.19.1–2. Following Theon, Ficino thinks of the sums in the series as being the result of the addition of the next odd number to the sum and not to the succession of the preceding odd numbers, e.g., 16=9+7 and not (5+3+1)+7, etc. See Michel, De Pythagore , pp. 304–311.


60

4, 9, 16, 25, and so on—coincide with the square products of the regular sequence of odd and even numbers—12 , 22 , 32 , 42 , 52 —numbers whose root is known, as chapter 10 explains.

B. The "unequilateral" series of numbers as sums begins with 2 as "the leader of the even numbers" and is the result of adding the even numbers to each other in regular sequence thus: 2, 2+4=6, 6+6=12, 12+8=20, 20+10=30, 30+12=42, and so on (6.40–44, 53–58).[48] The sums of this series—2, 6, 12, 20, 30, 42, 56, 72, 90, 110, 132, 156, and so on—are also, from another perspective, the unequilateral "long" products (i.e., products of immediately adjacent numbers—1x2, 2x3, 3x4, 4x5, 5x6, 6x7, 7x8, and so on). They are also, from a third perspective, the spousal numbers.

As products these unequilaterals are always even (and therefore feminine), because they result from an even number multiplying an odd (6.59–61). This is only true of course of the "long" and not the "oblong" unequilateral numbers, that is, of the products of two numbers differing only by 1 (1 having, I repeat, a unique and mystical significance that also pertains to numbers that differ by 1). With "oblong" numbers—for instance, with 35 as the product of 7x5—the situation is obviously different, since a third of the products will be odd (those which are the result of odd numbers multiplying odd) while two-thirds will be even (those which are the result of evens multiplying either evens or odds) (6.70–73). Ficino must nevertheless be concerned with the oblong numbers insofar as Plato's geometric number, being inclusive of all kinds of numbers, also contains this kind. In particular, he will have to confront 7x100 as we shall see.

Following Theon's Expositio 1.16,[49] Ficino then relates the equilateral to the unequilateral series by arguing that the equilaterals "contain" or "bind fast" the unequilaterals just as the odd numbers contain the even (9.15–25). His argument hinges once again on the notion of ratio. Between, say, 9 and 4, both of which are equilaterals, the mean is 6, an unequilateral; and the ratio of 9:6 and of 6:4 in each case is 3:2. Again between 16 and 9, both equilaterals, the mean is 12, an

[48] Cf. Theon, Expositio 1.13 (ed. Hiller, p. 27.7–13), and again Nicomachus, Introductio 2.19.1–2. Once more Ficino thinks of the sums in this series as being the result of the addition of the next even number to the sum and not to the succession of the preceding even numbers, e.g., 20=12+8 and not (6+4+2)+8. See Michel, De Pythagore , pp. 316–317.

[49] Ed. Hiller, pp. 28.16–30.7.


61

unequilateral; and the ratio of 16:12 and of 12:9 in each case is 4:3. In both these instances the equilaterals are said to contain or "bind fast" the unequilaterals, since the ratios between the mediate unequilateral and its two bracketing equilaterals are identical. But if we reverse the situation and regard the equilateral as bracketed by two unequilaterals, for instance 9 as bracketed by 12 and 6, then the unequilaterals do not contain the equilateral, because the accompanying ratios are not identical—12 to 9 being 4:3, but 9 to 6 being 3:2. Thus Ficino argues, the equilaterals "encompass and bind fast" the unequilateral (9.34–35). Again, note that, for the Pythagoreans, the 1 is an equilateral, although it is simple and all the other equilaterals are compound, while 2 is an unequilateral.

C. The third primary series, logically perhaps the first but treated third both by Theon and by Ficino and whose discovery the tradition attributed directly to Pythagoras, Ficino refers to as the trigon or triangle sequence.[50] He describes this in chapter 7 as the series of sums that results from the adding together of the odd and even numbers in regular succession, starting with the 1 since it bears "the trigonic power in itself" and is "as it were a trigon in power": 1, 1+2=3, 3+3=6, 6+4=10, 10+5=15, and so on. If we add adjacent trigons together, we arrive at sums that are also the successive square products of the whole numbers: 1+3=4, 3+6=9, 6+10=16, 10+15=25, and so on, the products one obtains, of course, from summing in the equilateral series.

IV. Throughout Ficino works with a set of terms concerned with ratio (logos ), or what he consistently thinks of as proportion (analogia ), though proportion, strictly speaking, involves at least two ratios and three terms, as we have seen. In the forefront of his mind are musical proportions and the resulting intervals, a subject he had already dealt with in some detail in his commentary on the Timaeus and elsewhere,[51] and the principles of which he had derived from Plato himself, from the commentaries on the Timaeus by Calcidius and by Proclus, and in all probability from the musical treatises of Augustine

[50] Cf. Theon, Expositio 1.19,23 (ed. Hiller, pp. 31.13–33.17, 37.7–38.15), and Nicomachus, Introductio 2.8.1–3. See Michel, De Pythagore , pp. 299 ff.

[51] For instance in his Philebus Commentary 1.28 (ed. Allen, pp. 264–269). See n. 1 above.


62

and Boethius, and this is to leave aside the possible mediating roles of various medieval sources. We should recall, furthermore, that Plato himself uses the harmony of the musical scale as a symbol of the harmony of the state in the Republic 4.443D and that both Theon and Boethius situate their studies of proportions in their accounts of music.[52]

Ficino's starting point for an examination of the cosmic and musical ratios is the celebrated passage, as we have seen, in the Timaeus on the lambda at 35B–36B and again at 43D. Between the prime cubes 27 and 8, he observes in chapter 3, Plato had postulated three intervals with 18 and 12 as the geometric means, the three "proportions" between 27 and 18, 18 and 12, and 12 and 8 being all in the same ratio of 3:2, that is, of one and a half to one.[53]

However, between these two prime cubes also exist the two "equilateral planes," 16 (42 ) and 9 ([3] ) from the equilateral sequence. And between these two equilaterals appears the unequilateral 12. Since the equilaterals contain the unequilateral, the proportions between 16 and 12 and between 12 and 9 are both in the same ratio of 4:3, that is, of one and a third to one.

Thus Plato's lambda of numbers implicitly links the two prime cubes by way of the two geometric means 18 and 12 and by way of the constant ratio of 3:2. But 16 and 9—the equilateral planes—are each linked to 12 in the ratio of 4:3 and thence in Ficino's terms "bind" it in.[54] The ratios pertaining to 18, however, Ficino ignores because of the primacy and importance of 12. For 12 is the sum of the "prime foundations" of the two ratios governing Plato's lambda, namely 4:3 and 3:2, in that 7 is the "foundation" or "root" of the ratio of 4:3, and 5 of the ratio of 3:2, the two roots together adding up to 12 (3.22–26). These two ratios are especially esteemed because they and the ratio 2:1 "accord with the perfection and steadfastness of things" (9.36–38). Moreover, Ficino argues, the sesquialteral is in accord with the ratio of 2:1 in that 2:1, 3:2, 2:2, 2:3, 1:2 form a se-

[52] Theon, Expositio 2, and Boethius, Institutio Musica 2. See Michel, De Pythagore , pp. 358n, 362–364.

[53] Sesquialter means half as much again, sesquitertius a third as much again, and so forth. But Ficino clearly thinks of the situation musically, that is, in terms of sesquialteral and sesquitertial ratios, and therefore in the form 3:2 and 4:3 (to parallel the double ratio of 2:1) and not in the form 1 1/2 to 1 or 1 1/3 to 1. Hence I have rendered the terms as ratios throughout. For the complex situation, see Michel, De Pythagore , pp. 348–362 (on the various relationships of inequality) and 365–411 (on proportions and means).

[54] Cf. Ficino's Timaeus Commentary 19 (Opera , p. 1446).


63

quence of what he refers to as "overcoming" and "overcome" ratios; and similarly with the sesquitertial ratio and 3:1 (4.3–16).[55]

The two ratios of 3:2 and 4:3 are also especially esteemed by Platonists because the one produces the musical consonance of diapente , the interval of the perfect fifth; the other that of diatesseron , the interval of the perfect fourth. From them is produced the universal harmony known as the diapason , the interval of the octave, "the most celebrated of harmonies" (3.26–31), which Ficino thinks of traditionally as a "double proportion" in that (4x3):(3x2) gives us the ratio 2:1. Once again 12 is the important number, for it contains 5 and 7, the "roots" of the diapante (as 3+2) and of the diatesseron (as 4+3), and it is the sum of their being "compounded" that is added together. From Ficino's Pythagorean viewpoint 12 also contains the two ratios internally in that, having dissolved the one root of 5 into 3 and 2, we can double the 3 and then double it again to produce 12. Similarly, having dissolved the other root of 7 into 4 and 3, we can triple the 4 to again produce 12. Thus 4, 3, and 2, the "parts" of 7 and 5, when all "mixed together," produce 12. Accordingly, both by addition and by multiplication 12 contains the 7 and 5. Additionally, it is the result of multiplying the first two prime numbers 3 and 4 together—1 and 2 we recall are not numbers, 1 being the source of all numbers and 2 being "a confused multitude" (3.40–42). Ficino sees the presence of a great "mystery" here in that 7 is the number of the planets, and 5 the number of the zones of the world—the four zones of the four elements and the zone of heaven (3.59–60).[56] Five is also the "prime origin" of the perfect shape of the circle in that, whether squared or cubed, it ends with the number 5 and therefore is the first circular number (3.61–64).

V. Before turning to Ficino's attempted solution of Plato's account of the geometric number, let me end this review of his arithmological assumptions and his presentation of material from Theon's Expositio , by addressing briefly the traditional core of arithmology, the symbolic associations of the first ten numbers, the decad. Ficino does not present us with a schematic account here (or as far as I know elsewhere), but

[55] This provides us with a clue to Ficino's interpretation of Plato's phrase in the Republic 8.546B5, "dunamenai te kai dunasteuomenai ."

[56] And not, we might note, of the two frozen and the two temperate zones and the one torrid zone, the five climatic zones of the earth. Cf. Ficino's Critias epitome (Opera , p. 1486).


64

the decad figures prominently at times in his thinking, and he certainly assumed that Plato took its Pythagorean dimensions seriously. The nature of his debts to particular ancient or medieval numerologists I leave to others to explore,[57] but he was obviously familiar with the sections on the decad in Theon's Expositio 2.40–49.

ONE, chapter 8 argues, is the principle of all numbers and dimensions and therefore most resembles the principle of the universe itself, the One,[58] since it too remains entirely eminent and simple even as it procreates offspring. All the even numbers proceed from the 1 and the odd numbers turn back towards it. All dimensions issue from it as from a point. It is the substance of all numbers in that any number is 1 repeated. Hence 1 is the "measure" of all numbers whether odd or even, simple (that is, measured by the 1 alone) or compound (that is, also measured, i.e., divided, by a number other than 1 as 4 by 2). The 1 is like the maker of the world who imposes form on the 2 as on indeterminate matter.[59] Indeed Archytas, Ficino recalls, had supposed that the 1 was the Idea of the odd numbers and that the 2 was therefore the Idea of the even numbers. Yet the 1 "is both none of the numbers because of its most simple eminence, and all the numbers because it has the effective power of all numbers." Hence it has no "parts" and is neither even nor odd; for added to an even it makes it an odd and thus appears odd, and added to an odd it makes it an even and thus appears even. Ficino refers to Aristotle's lost work The Pythagorean here in affirming that the Pythagoreans preferred the 1 to be odd because the odd, male number (unlike the even, female number) changes the number to which it is added, making the previously odd into an even, the previously even into an odd; as such the 1 is consid-

[57] However, I doubt that he knew the most detailed of the "Platonic" arithmologies, the Pseudo-Iamblichean Theologumena . It contains, however, precisely the kind of Pythagorean number lore he was interested in, and I have cross-referenced it for that reason.

[58] Cf. Theon, Expositio 2.40 (ed. Hiller, pp. 99.24–100.8). The Theologumena 14.7 and Proclus in his Republic Commentary 13 (ed. Kroll, 2:21) both declare that the monad is sacred to Zeus (but for Proclus, see n. 38 above).

[59] Cf. Ficino's Philebus Commentary 2.1 (ed. Allen, pp. 386–387): "God is the measure of all things" who as the infinite limit imprints the limit in them—Ficino is contrasting (and reconciling) the Parmenides ' description of God as the infinite with the Philebus 's as the measure and limit (p. 389). The One "encloses all, forms all, sustains all, circumscribes all" (p. 387). By contrast, the infinite Plato is speaking of in the Philebus (as in the Timaeus ) is matter itself, which is formed "by a certain beneficent glance of the divine countenance" (p. 389). This matter is the "necessity" that is formed by intelligence, the pure potentiality that submits to God's act (p. 391). In general see the Theologumena 1.3–7.13 (on the monad) and 7.14–14.12 (on the dyad).


65

ered the prime equilateral. The 1 is indivisible, for when it appears to be divided it is in fact being miraculously doubled. Thus as the principle of "identity, equality, and likeness" it again resembles God. It has a "marvelous likeness" to Him also in that however much you multiply or divide it by itself, you neither increase nor diminish it; for, without altering itself, it is the square, the cube, and all other greater powers within itself.[60]

TWO the Pythagoreans wished to be indeterminate, says Ficino (6.46–47). As the dyad it is the "first multitude" (8.77–80) but not exactly the first number, though it is the begetter of the even, female numbers and as such is the prime unequilateral (as 2x1). Even so, it is the "principle" of no one figure, as the 1 is of the circle, or the 3 of the triangle and hence of all rectilinear figures. Archytas, as we have seen, had supposed 2 to be the Idea of the even numbers; but in Neoplatonic ontology, the dyad is identified with the "infinite" or "indefinite" (to apeiron ).[61] The two's negative connotations carry over for Ficino, following Plato in the Laws 4.717AB, to all the even numbers and make them subordinate to the odd.

Given the unique status of the 1 and the 2 as in a way nonnumbers, the THREE, Ficino declares, again citing Archytas, is the first number proper; as such it is made from the 1, and from the confused multitude, the otherness, the degeneration from the 1 that is the 2 (8.77–80). As the first number, it is necessarily the principle of all rectilinear figures (6.49–51); for the 3 is the first trigon, and the triangle is the first of the rectilinear figures (and there are of course three types of triangle—the equilateral, the isosceles and the scalene—and three types of angle—the obtuse, the acute, and the right angle). God "rejoices" in the 3 since it is "hinged" upon the 1 as 1+1+1. Therefore, it is the first of the three preeminent male numbers, the other two being 7 (3+1+3) and 9 (3+1+1+1+3) (6.88–92). It is of course the number of the Christian Trinity and thus of the "footsteps" (vestigia ) of that Trinity in all creation.[62]

[60] The analogies between the monad and the One as the ultimate metaphysical principle were as integral to the Christian philosophical tradition as to Pythagoreanism; see Theon, Expositio 1.3–4 (ed. Hiller, pp. 18.3–21.19) and the Theologumena 3.1 ff. Ficino had expatiated endlessly on the theme from his earliest involvement with Platonism; see, for instance, the earlier versions of the Philebus Commentary 2.1 (ed. Allen, pp. 394–395) dating from the 1460s.

[61] Again see Ficino's Philebus Commentary 2.1–4 and unattached chapter 3 (ed. Allen, pp. 384–425, 430–433). Among his sources were Proclus's Platonic Theology 3.7–9, In Timaeum 1.176 (ed. Diehl), and In Parmenidem 1118.9–1124.37 (ed. Cousin, 2d ed., Paris, 1864). Cf. the Theologumena 7.3–13, 8.5 ff., 12.9 ff.

[62] Augustine's De Trinitate 9–15 was assuredly Ficino's principal source here.

Among notable threes for Ficino and his contemporaries were the biblical three patriarchs, three magi, and three Marys, and the pagan three Graces, three Fates, the various triform or triple-headed deities such as Hermes, Cerberus, and Hecate, and the many threefold invocations and libations in classical literature. For the latter cf. the final summa of Ficino's Philebus Commentary (ed. Allen, p. 518), which declares that Socrates at 66D is offering up sacrificially "the third libation to the savior Zeus (Jovi conservatori )"; for "the ancient priests customarily poured the libation bowl thrice, declaring that we need god [Jupiter] the savior not only in the beginning of our affairs and of our life, but in the middle too and end." Ficino was also drawn to the Chaldaean trinity of Ohrmazd, Mithra, and Ahriman (Oromazes, Mithras, Areimanius) which he encountered in Plutarch's De Iside 46 (Moralia 369E). In general, see Theon, Expositio 2.42 (ed. Hiller, pp. 100.13–101.10); the Theologumena 14.13–19.20; Ficino's own De Amore 2.1; and Pico, Heptaplus 6, proem; also Edgar Wind, Pagan Mysteries in the Renaissance , rev. ed. (New York, 1968), pp. 241–255.


66

FOUR is the first square number and the first number to have two means. It is the number of man's ages, of the humors and seasons, and of the elements; and it refers, says Ficino, to the "revolution" or "commutation" of the four elemental spheres which is "in a way intercepted" in the plane (17.14–15, 18–20). Hence 4 is not a wholly circular number like 5 or 6. In Pythagorean lore the "sacred quaternary" is the four numbers 1, 2, 3, and 4—the tetraktys—since together they add up to 10.[63]

FIVE, the proportional arithmetic mean of the decad according to Theon (2.44), is the first of the fully circular numbers and refers to the "period," that is, to the circuit in general, of the planets (17.17–18). For the planetary region is the fifth, the celestial region above the four regions of the elemental spheres, the region made from Aristotle's fifth element, the aether. In the Timaeus 55C Plato had identified the fifth regular solid, the dodecahedron, the figure significantly with twelve pentagonal faces, with the world.[64] Aristotle says

[63] For disquisitions on the 4, see Ficino's Timaeus Commentary 20–24 and 26 (Opera , pp. 1446–1450); Theon, Expositio 2.38 (ed. Hiller, pp. 93.25–99.16)—on the eleven quaternaries; and the Theologumena 20.1–30.15; also Dupuis, Théon , pp. 385–386. Ficino makes no mention here of many other associations: with the tetragrammaton, the Evangelists, the corners of the world, the winds, the kinds of animals and of plants, the rivers of paradise and those of the underworld, the cardinal virtues, the horses of the Apocalypse, etc.; and with such fourfold triplicities as those of the angelic orders, the tribes of Israel, the zodiacal signs, and the apostles. See Heninger, Touches of Sweet Harmony , pp. 82–83, 151–156.

[64] Cf. the Theologumena 31.4–7, 32.17–20, 34.11 ff. and Ficino's Timaeus Commentary 44 (misnumbered 41) (Opera , p. 1464v). Ficino, erroneously, sees the twelve pentagonal faces as each divided into five equilateral triangles, which are in turn each divided into six half-equilateral triangles, making 360 such triangles in all. This equals the number of degrees in the zodiac, while 360x10 equals the number of the great year. His source here was almost certainly Plutarch's Platonic Questions 5.1 (Moralia 1003CD).


67

that the Pythagoreans called 5 (as 3+2) the marriage or wedding number,[65] though they also associated it (and 4 and 8!) with justice.[66]

SIX is called by the Pythagoreans the "spousal number" because "in its conception a male number joins with a female" (4.41–42).[67] As 3x2 it is thus the first product of the first even number and the first odd (given the 1's unique status). However, as the first of the perfect numbers, the first to equal the sum of its factors, and as the higher of the first two purely circular numbers (as 6-36-216), it is also a symbol of divine generation and "contains the circuit itself of divine generation" (17.3–17).[68] This refers, I take it, to the six days of Creation, to the six intervals between the seven planetary spheres,[69] and to the "circuit of the firmament," that is, to the revolution of the sphere of the fixed stars above the fifth region of the planets which is in turn above the four elementary regions. Working with the Platonic order of the planets (or rather with its Porphyrian variation),[70] Ficino uses 6 to plot certain critical astronomical durations or distances in the sense of spans. Thus in six steps from the firmament we reach Venus, from Saturn we reach the Sun, and from the Moon we reach Jupiter. Since

[65] Cf. Aristotle apud Alexander of Aphrodisias, In Metaphysicam 39.8 (fr. 203)—see G. S. Kirk, J. E. Raven, and M. Schofield, The Presocratic Philosophers , 2d. ed. (Cambridge, 1983), p. 336 (no. 436); also the Theologumena 30.19, 41.12–14. But see SIX (as 3x2) below. Five and six are linked insofar as one is 3+2 and the other 3x2, and insofar as they are the first circular numbers.

[66] Cf. Proclus, Republic Commentary 13 (ed. Kroll, 2:22); also the Theologumena 35.6 ff., 40.5–9 (and, in general, 30.16–41.20) and Iamblichus, In Nicomachi Arith. Introd. 16.11–20. Again, other associations—with the five senses, the five precipitations, the five books of Moses, the five wounds of Christ, and so on—are not adduced. For disquisitions on the quinarium , the five elements and the five universal genera (from the Sophist ), see Ficino's Timaeus Commentary 24 and 28 (Opera , pp. 1449.1, 1451.2–1452).

[67] Cf. Theon, Expositio 2.45 (ed. Hiller, p. 102.4–6); and the Theologumena 43.5–9, "it is also called 'marriage' in the strict sense that it arises not by addition, as the pentad does [i.e., 5=3+2], but by multiplication" (trans. Waterfield, p. 75). In his Timaeus Commentary 12 (Opera , p. 1443.2) Ficino observes that Pythagoras had agreed with Moses "probans senarium numerum genesi nuptiisque accommodari, unde et Gamon appellat propterea quod partes suae iuxta positae ipsum gignant similemque reddant genitum genitori." Six is also the mean between the prime square numbers 4 and 9.

[68] On the perfection of the hexad, see the Theologumena 42.19–43.3 (and, in general, 42.18–54.9), and Augustine, City of God 11.30, and De Genesi ad Litteram passim (the most authoritative for Ficino of many hexaemeral commentaries).

[69] Cf. the Theologumena 48.10–14, 50.5–6.

[70] The Porphyrian order goes: Moon, Sun, Venus, Mercury, Mars, Jupiter, Saturn, whereas the strictly Platonic order reverses the positions of Venus and Mercury. See my Platonism , pp. 118–119, n. 17, for further references.


68

these are the three "vivific" planets, the 6 is therefore associated with propitious periods in our lives, particularly the sixth month of gestation, and, even more importantly still the sixth, the jovian, year and its multiples.[71] The 6 is the key number to be taken into account when determining the opportune time for marrying and begetting and for embarking on any kind of project, material or intellectual. Even so, the 6 pertains more to the class of the "divine" than to that of the human; for, like the divine, the 6 is neither wanting (deficient) nor overflowing (abundant) and as such it is tempered equally and consists in, in the literal Latin sense of stands firm in, its parts and powers (17.57–62). Finally, it is the key to the ratios governing the Platonic lambda, being the first of the geometric means.[72]

SEVEN is the number of the planets, which constitute the fifth, the celestial, world zone; and the 7 added to the 5 composes 12. There are seven terms in the lambda (associated in the Timaeus 34B–37A with the planets and thus with the harmonies of the soul), and each of the two progressions in the lambda has four terms plus three intervals. There are also seven planetary modes.[73] Along with the 3 and the 9,

[71] And we should recall the importance of the cube of 6 in determining the period between reincarnations. See Chapter 1, n. 82 above.

[72] See n. 6 above. An Orphic verse familiar to Ficino from Plato's Philebus 66C reads, "With the sixth generation ceases the glory of my song" (ed. O. Kern, Fragmenta Orphicorum [Berlin, 1922], frg. 14; cf. Plutarch, De E apud Delphos 15 [Moralia 391D], and Proclus, In Rempublicam 2.100.23). He cites this verse in his Philebus Commentary 1.27, 2.2, and summa 65 (ed. Allen, pp. 257, 405, 518), in the first instance quoting the Greek and arguing that "Nature's progress stops at this, the sixth link of the golden chain introduced by Homer." In summa 65 he entertains the possibility that Plato's reference to the Orphic "sixth generation" may be to the Good Itself; for, he concludes, "Orpheus orders the hymns to end at the sixth generation, at the ineffable [Good] as it were. We see that the number 6 is celebrated by Orpheus as the end, as it was by Moses. For in the first ten numbers, this is the perfect number, being compounded from its parts disposed in order, that is from 1, 2, and 3." These comments point not only to Ficino's subtle sense of Platonic play but also, given the summa's heading which reads "Jupiter is the savior of the sixth grade or level," to his early association of Jove with 6; and this is despite the fact that in his ontology he identifies Jove with Soul (or with Soul in Mind), not with the Absolute Good that is the One. See my Platonism , pp. 125–128, 238–240, 244–245, 250–251, 252; and Chapter 4 below.

We should also recall that Ficino saw Plato as the sixth, and therefore as the most perfect, in the line of the six ancient theologians, the prisci theologi : Zoroaster, Hermes Trismegistus, Orpheus, Aglaophemus, Pythagoras, Plato. See, for example, his Philebus Commentary 1.17, 26 (ed. Allen, pp. 181, 247), and his Platonic Theology 6.1 (ed. Marcel, 1:224).

[73] See Ficino's De Vita 3.21. Wind, Pagan Mysteries , p. 268, observes that among the seven planetary modes "only the Dorian, associated with the sun and thus with

Apollo, is pure. Placed in the centre of the planets it secures the symmetry of the other six by dividing them into two triads."


69

the 7 is one of the three conspicuous male numbers because it exists on either side of its 1 as 3+1+3 (6.91–92). But Ficino also accepts the idea that it is sacred to Athena, being the first virgin number to succeed the first spousal number; and as such it is endowed with a marvelous property, as Theon says, since alone in the decad it has no multiple and no divisor.[74] There are of course seven days to the week, and a lunar quarter spans seven days. In ancient and medieval numerology there are seven orifices in the head and seven viscera; and Ficino refers elsewhere to the topos of man's seven ages[75] and to the seven metals associated with the seven planets.[76] It was also an important number, as he knew, in embryology, in human development theory with its climacterics, and in fever theory.[77] In the Bible it is particularly prominent in the Book of Revelation,[78] and it is traditionally the number of the deadly sins, of the virtues, and of the blessed sacraments.

For the Pythagoreans, EIGHT is a number associated with egalitarian justice, like 4 but for different reasons (6.93–94). But its primary significance for Ficino is its status as the number of the celestial

[74] Expositio 2.46 (ed. Hiller, 103.1–5): "thaumastên echei dunamin ." Cf. the Theologumena 54.11, 71.3–10; Macrobius, In Somnium Scipionis 1.6.11; Plutarch, De Iside et Osiride 10 (Moralia 354F); Proclus, In Timaeum 168C (ed. Diehl, 2:95.5); also Vergil, Aeneid 1.94: "O terque quaterque beati."

Plutarch, on the other hand, in his De E apud Delphos 17 (Moralia 391F), says that 7 is consecrated to Apollo, though Apollo is usually identified with the One (as for instance in the De Iside 10 cited above). We might note that there were traditionally Seven Sages and that the Theologumena 70.24, 71.10–12 says that 7 is the number of kairos , of the appropriate time (cf. Aristotle fr. 203 apud Alexander In Meta . 38.16 as cited by Kirk-Raven-Schofield, p. 331).

[75] Opera , pp. 1919–1920 in his translation of Proclus's In Alcibiadem 90–91 (ed. Westerink). Cf. Theon, Expositio 2.46 (ed. Hiller, pp. 103.19–104.19); and the Theologumena 55.13–56.7.

[76] See Ficino's argumentum for the Critias (Opera , p. 1486): gold for the Sun, silver for the Moon, lead for Saturn, electrum for Jupiter, iron and bronze for Mars, orichalcum (copper or brass) for Venus, and stagnum (an alloy of silver and lead) for Mercury.

[77] See Ficino's Platonic Theology 17.2 (ed. Marcel, 3:155), De Vita 2.20.1–17 (ed. and trans. Carol V. Kaske and John R. Clark, Marsilio Ficino: Three Books on Life [Binghamton, N.y., 1989]), cf. Theon, Expositio 2.46 (ed. Hiller, p. 104.9–12) and the Theologumena 55.5–7, 61.5–63.5, 64.17–67.2, 67.14–71.3 (with further references).

[78] As the number of the churches of Asia (1:4), of the spirits before God's throne (1:4), of the golden candlesticks (1:12), of the stars in the right hand of the Son of Man (1:16), of the angels of the churches who are symbolized by the candlesticks (1:20), of the number of the seals, of the angels with the seven trumpets and the seven plagues (5:1–8.2, 15:1), of the horns and eyes of the Lamb (5:6), of the heads of the beast

upon which sits the whore of Babylon (17.3), and of the world kingdoms (we are now in the sixth age) (17:9–10). Jude's Epistle declares that Enoch was seventh in the line from Adam (1:14).

We should recall that Pico's Heptaplus (1489) is a sevenfold narration of the six days of Creation and is divided into seven books which are subdivided into seven chapters. On God's resting on the seventh day, see Ficino's Timaeus Commentary 17 (Opera , p. 1445.1) and Augustine's City of God 11.31.


70

spheres and the octave, and as the first of the "solid" numbers, being the cube of 2.[79]

NINE is the number sacred to the Muses,[80] and there are nine heavenly choirs in Christian angelology.[81] In the Proclian tradition it is the number of the "like" and the "same," since it is the square of the first odd number,[82] and there are of course nine months to gestation.

Besides being the number of the commandments, TEN is the universal number as the sum of the sacred quaternary of 1, 2, 3, and 4 (and thus a trigon). It is the origin of the other universal numbers, that is, of 100, 1000, 10,000 (the myriad), 1,000,000, and so on.[83] Theon says that 10 is imperfect, even though it is sometimes thought

[79] Cf. Ficino's Republic 4 epitome (Opera , p. 1403) which refers to the Pythagorean 8, the Orphic 8, and the Egyptian 8. In general see Theon, Expositio 2.47 (ed. Hiller, pp. 104.20–106.2); and the Theologumena 72.1–75.4.

[80] See Ficino's argumentum for the Ion (Opera , p. 1283) and Platonic Theology 4.1 (ed. Marcel, 1:164–165); also my Platonism , pp. 28–30.

[81] For medieval Christianity it was the authority of the Pseudo-Dionysius's On the Celestial Hierarchy that had fixed the ranks and orders of the angels at three hierarchies of three choirs each; cf. Ficino, De Raptu Pauli 6 (ed. Marcel, in Ficin: Théologie 3:352), and Pico, Heptaplus 2, proem.

[82] Cf. Proclus, In Rempublicam 2.80.23–26 (ed. Kroll); and the Theologumena 78.14. Plato was said to be ninth in succession from Pythagoras. In his Phaedrus Commentary, summa 24 (ed. Allen, pp. 165–169), Ficino addresses the problem of the nine lives introduced in the Phaedrus 248C–E; see my Platonism , pp. 174–179.

[83] Cf. Ficino's Phaedrus Commentary, summa 25 (ed. Allen, pp. 168–171). On the universal nature of the decad, see Ps.-Aristotle, Problemata 15.3.910b23 ff.; and the Theologumena 79.16–81.3, 82.10–85.23 (this includes an important fragment by Speusippus [fr. 4, Lang] on the Pythagorean numbers). For the myriad, cf. Pico, Heptaplus 3.6, paraphrasing Daniel 7:10: "Ten thousand stood before him [the Ancient of days], and a thousand thousands ministered unto him."

The Republic 10.615AB declares optimistically that 10x10 is man's natural life-span; and Pythagoras is said to have lived for almost a hundred years (see Iamblichus, De Vita Pythagorica 36.265). In a brevis annotatio inserted between his translations of books 5 and 6, Pier Candido Decembrio had argued that Plato's ten books represent the ten decades of this natural life (see Hankins, Plato in the Italian Renaissance 1:133, 135 and n.). However, in his epitome for book 1 (Opera , p. 1396), Ficino supposes, presumably on Pythagorean grounds (see n. 84 below), that Plato had elected to write the Republic in ten books because ten is "the most whole" (integerrimus ) of all the numbers.


71

of as a perfect number by Pythagoreans,[84] who referred to it as "the unity of the second rank," the 1 being the unity of the first rank, the 100 the unity of the third rank, and the 1000 the unity of the fourth.85

VI. While traditional arithmology treats of the decad alone, there is one other number of particular importance to Ficino here, given his obsession with the Timaeus 's lambda as a model, and given the role he assigns to the harmonic ratios in preparing us for an understanding of the fatal geometric number. For set over and against the ordinary world of 10 and its multiples is the duodecimal world governed by 12, the number presiding over Plato's last book, the Laws , where, Ficino maintained, Plato had spoken for the first time, apart from his Letters , in his own person.[86]

Though the second of the spousal numbers as 3x4,[87] 12 is the first and "prince" of the "abundant" numbers (4.38–40), meaning, as we have seen, that the sum of its factors—that is, of 6+4+3+2+1—exceeds itself, in this instance by as much as a third again. As such, it designates fertility. Ficino claims that 12 is the number "secretly" venerated in the eighth book of the Republic , while it is openly venerated in several other dialogues (3.42–44). In the twelve books of the Laws (at 5.745B–E,746D, 6.771A–C, and 8.848CD), 12 is the number into which the Athenian Stranger divides the state's capital city, and then divides and subdivides its surrounding agricultural districts and its 5040 citizens; and each twelfth portion of territory and people is dedicated to one of twelve gods—the ideal state has in fact a duodecimal structure. In the Phaedo 110B ff. Plato affirms that the globe resembles a ball made from twelve pieces. In the Timaeus at 55C4–6 he speaks of the fifth "combination" or figure which later Platonists iden-

[84] Theon, Expositio 1.32 (ed. Hiller, p. 46.12–14) and Nicomachus, in his Introductio 2.22.1, say that the Pythagoreans thought the 10 perfect (as the sum of 1+2+3+4 and not as the sum of its factors). But Theon goes on to declare later at 2.49 (ed. Hiller, 106.7–10) that it "contains in itself the nature of both even and odd, of that which is in motion and that which is at rest, of good and of evil."

[85] Cf. Iamblichus, In Nicomachi Arith. Introd. 88.22–26 (ed. Pistelli).

[86] See his epitome for Laws 1 (Opera , p. 1488).

[87] In an interesting passage in his Commentary on the First Book of Euclid's Elements 1.36, Proclus observes that the dodecad is the product of the triad and the tetrad and that it "ends in the single monad, the sovereign principle of Zeus, for Philolaus says that the angle of the dodecagon belongs to Zeus, because in unity Zeus contains the entire number of the dodecad." Ficino had access to this passage, though he does not cite it.


72

tified with the mysterious dodecahedron that the Demiurge had used for "the delineation of the universe" with the twelve zodiacal signs, as we have seen; and at 58C–61C he speaks of the twelve world spheres and the twelve parts of the elemental spheres (each of the four spheres being divided into a higher, middle, and lower zone). In the Phaedrus 246E–247E Plato describes the twelve orders of the gods and their ascent as charioteers to the outer convex rim of heaven, there to gaze upwards at the supercelestial place. And in the Critias 109B ff. and 113BC he refers to the ancient prediluvian division of the earth by the gods into twelve allotments (at least in the Neoplatonic interpretation). In short, Ficino associates 12 with several major texts, including as we saw earlier the Epinomis , and assumes it to be a number fraught with especial significance for Plato quite apart from its being the number of the chief Olympian deities, of the signs of the zodiac, of the months, and so forth.

Ficino writes that 12 is the governor "of the universal world form, of the human form, and of the form of the state," because it is the number that presides over the increase and mutations of all things, being the double of 6, the first of the perfect numbers (3.53–58). Yet 12 is also the sum of 7 and 5–7 being the number of the planets and the "root" of the sesquitertial ratio as we have seen, and 5 being the zones of the world and the root of the sesquialteral ratio. Hence 12 is the most "accordant with" the world's orb and is the traditional number of the world spheres in Chaldaean-Ptolemaic cosmology. Twelve is particularly associated with the planets presiding over life: the Sun, Jupiter, Venus, and the Moon—the founts of vitality—whose orbital paths significantly are measured in twelves, the Sun and Venus completing their orbits (around the Earth) in twelve months, Jupiter in twelve years, and the Moon waxing (and then waning) in twelve days in her course through her twenty-eight mansions, and thereby establishing twelve as the months in the year (3.64–68). No wonder, writes Ficino, that such a number was observed by the "Prophets and in sacred writings."[88]

We are now in a position to follow Ficino's unraveling of the mystery of the fatal geometric number.

[88] Apart from there being twelve tribes of Israel and twelve apostles, in the Book of Revelation twelve is the number of the gates of the New Jerusalem inscribed with the names of the twelve tribes, each having 12,000 people (and thus 144,000 [12 x10 ] is the number sealed to be saved) (7:4–8). Revelation also speaks of the woman with the crown of twelve stars (12:1) and of the twelve kinds of fruit on the tree of life (22:2).


73

VII. The Republic book 8 speaks of a human or imperfect number that has four terms and therefore three intervals or distances, the terms being related to one another in certain ratios or proportions. In addressing the challenge of identifying this number, Ficino plays with the circumspect notion, given his knowledge of book 9, that there may perhaps be several such "fatal" numbers—not to be confused necessarily as we have seen with "spousal" numbers.[89] As numbers that have an "immense power to produce both good and not good progeny" (13.35–37), the fatal numbers must all be contrasted with the perfect (or perfecting) number that Plato had begun the discussion with and that presides over divine and therefore wholly good progeny, a number that was itself either the first in, or at least one of, the select class of such numbers.

Plato is most drawn, Ficino argues, to two particular fatal numbers, since they "best agree with the universe" and "embrace the consonances," that is, the universal Pythagorean harmonies that govern the motions of the nest of its spheres (3.108–109). Following Aristotle, Ficino finds it especially important that Plato had arrived at a cubed number, since cubing constitutes raising to the "highest" power, raising to even higher powers being merely an imitation or complication of cubing—trinitarian assumptions are obviously to the fore here as are the associations of three with the classical Fates and specifically with Plato's presentation of them.

A. In chapter 3 Ficino first considers the candidature of 729, a number ending in 9 which is celebrated from Ficino's viewpoint significantly and not coincidentally in book 9 of the Republic at 587E ff., the only other passage in the entire work which casts a light, however dim, on the problem of the computation of the fatal number alluded to in book 8.[90] This "great and fatal" number 729 is seen as the product of cubing 9—the number symbolizing the nine celestial spheres, those, that is, of the planets, of the fixed stars, and of the primum mo-

[89] Compare the heading for the Expositio with that for the Commentarius as a whole (though neither heading may be Ficino's).

[90] In his epitome for book 9 (Opera , pp. 1426–1427), Ficino merely observes, "Inter haec casu quodam nescio quid interserit mathematicum, cuius declarationem ex commentariis in Timaeum accipies opportunius" (p. 1427). The fact that the number begins with 7, the number of the planets, and ends in 29, the number of days in which it takes the Moon to catch up with the Sun, would not have been lost on him. It is, incidentally, the seventh term in the series 1-3-9-27-81-243-729; and in the De animae procreatione 31 (Moralia 1028B), Plutarch declares it is the number of the Sun.


74

bile (3.77–80; 14.6–11). It is described in the ninth book as a measure of the interval separating the king from the tyrant and therefore as "an overwhelming expression of the distance that separates the just from the unjust in regard to pleasure and pain." "A true calculation," it is "a number which nearly concerns human life," being one less than the total number of days and nights in a year. Moreover, it is a circular number in that 9 is both its beginning (its root) and its end (its last digit), though, like 4, it is intercepted in its plane of 81.[91] Finally, while it has a cube root of 9, it also has a square root of 27; momentously it is endowed, in other words, with two roots that are themselves powers of 3.

B. Nonetheless, for Ficino the "principally fatal number" is not 9 raised to the third power or its equivalent 27 raised to the second power, but rather 12 raised to the third power, namely 1728 (which is also the product of 8x12x18, the first three numbers at the base of the Platonic lambda).[92] Since the last digit of 1728 is 8, 1728 is appropriately the subject of the eighth book (728 being one less than 729, the subject of the ninth book!). Ficino also finds it mathematically witty that Plato had begun his presentation of this fatal number in the eighth book by adducing 6, the first of the perfect numbers and the lambda's key, and had then ended the number with 28, the second of the perfect numbers (15.42–45). He is postulating, in other words, the presence not only of the manifest parts of a number, namely its factors, but of what he calls the "hidden" or secret parts also, those that constitute, as we shall see, its beginning, middle, and end.

The cube of 12 is both "fatal," that is, concerned with the marking out and the governing of time, and "universal" or compendious in that it embraces odds and evens, equilaterals and unequilaterals (both longs and oblongs), planes and solids, laterals and diagonals, and the better and worse consonances (13.31–35). Its compendiousness renders it "a discordant concord," appropriately so since it presides over

[91] Plato's reported death at the age of 81 is therefore numerologically significant, not least because 81 is the square of the months of gestation in the womb; see Seneca, De Senectute 5, and Dante, Convivio 4.24. In his Vita Platonis (Opera , p. 770.2; trans. in Letters 3:46), Ficino observes that the Magi saw 81 as "the most excellent number," being 9x9. Plotinus, incidentally, died at the age of 66. Pythagoras, Plato, and Plotinus thus offered three options for a philosophical life-span and Ficino selected 66 for himself!

[92] One is led to speculate whether the sesquitertial ratio between the two roots of 1728 and 729, namely 12:9, was of any significance to him (note wording of 3.77–82).


75

the discordant concord of the realms of quality, generation, and decay (15.33–36). Moreover, because its root of 12 is the first of the increasing or abundant numbers, 1728 is abundantly abundant—is the increasing number's increase to the third degree, to the absolute degree of increase. And, because its root contains the two harmonies of the perfect fourth 4:3 and the perfect fifth 3:2 in the sense that added together they make 12, the number of the diapason, 1728 too contains them. Indeed, it "extends" them still further, Ficino writes, and therefore "best agrees with the universe" (3.93–97). After 1728 years (and Ficino ignores the possibility that the number could apply to any set of temporal units—days, months, seasons, centuries), the circle of Fate reaches its turning point, and we enter upon a period of decline. Accompanying such a turning point are the various signs and wonders that augur the eventual end of a duration double that span of 1728 years, a duration of 3456 years, though neither Plato nor Ficino mentions such a duration.[93] Both durations are obviously considerably less than the cycle of the great year as defined by Plato in the Timaeus 39D as the time taken by the Sun, the Moon, and the rest of the planets to return to the same relative positions, a cycle governed by "the perfect number of time" (D3–4) and to which, as we have seen, Ficino had already assigned the traditional value of 36,000 years.[94]

Ficino asks why the fatal number is referred to as "proportional" and as "geometric" (13.35–36). It is proportional because it contains the musical proportions contained in 12, but it is geometric because it is the cube of the sum of the sides of the Pythagoreans' beautiful rectangular scalene with its sides of 3, 4, and 5 (and 5 can be defined, as we have seen, as the "root" of the ratio 3:2 and 7 as the root of the ratio 4:3). Since it contains the musical proportions, and since as a cube it is the beautiful triangle triangled as it were, it has an immense power to "abound" with temporal progeny good and bad, to abound with opportunities and occasions. Since numbers in the world ages and human ages should be carefully observed, writes Ficino at the end

[93] Of course, it might not be that symmetrical, and no one actually declares that 1728 is halfway through a cycle. Theoretically it might instead take double time, or triple or quadruple or whatever, to decline from the "abundant" point, or even some fractional span like time and a half, time and an eighth—the possibilities are limitless but unlikely.

A remote possibility is 46,656, the product we recall from n. 6 above of the numbers at the base of the Platonic lambda, since 8x12x18=1728=12 and 1728x27=46656 (i.e., 12 x3 , or 216 or 6 x6 , or 6 x6 x6 , or 6 ).

[94] See Chapter 1, n. 24 above.


76

of chapter 13, and because a praiseworthy number signals the opportunity for fecundity, an unpraiseworthy one the occasion for evil and sterility, this number, which is praiseworthy and unpraiseworthy equally, must be observed before all others. It is the most sublime and the most terrible instrument of Fate, is indeed the threefold number of the three Fates. For Ficino finds it significant: first that Plato had elected three components for the fatal number, second that he had concealed three different kinds of a hundred in it, and third that he had made it the third power of another number. In sum, Ficino thinks of Plato's fatal number as itself fatally—that is, triply—threefold, a fatal companion if you will of the 9 and its threefold powers.

C. Let us now turn to what Ficino calls the three "hidden" parts of 1728, the second of which involves him in some ingenious extrapolation.

i. The first such part is 1000. Ficino had argued earlier that 12 embraces 10 in the ratio of 6:5 in that 12=(5x2)+2; and thus "best agrees with the universe," 10 being the first of the universal numbers as the product of the first four numbers, the Pythagorean tetraktys (3.82–89). Hence 12 raised to the third power must likewise embrace the universe betokened by 10 raised also to the third power.[95] The 1000 is therefore the universal number raised to the fatal third or solid power.[96] In chapter 14 Ficino speculates that "perhaps" it signifies the firmament "hidden in a way in (among?) the stars," the stars themselves being the fabled myriad of the 10,000, i.e., 104 (14.13–14; cf. 3.97). Ficino knew the myriad had been celebrated particularly in the Phaedrus at 248E ff.;[97] but here he adduces it not only as the number of the "numberless crowd" of the stars—"numberless" because difficult to number, not because the stars are infinite in number[98] —but also as "the more ample" number, the limit, if you will, of the realm of planes just as the million is the limit of the realm of solids (14.18–22). The myriad can be unfolded, chapter 15 will subtly ar-

[95] Would Ficino have seen any numerological significance in Moses giving ten commandments to the twelve tribes of Israel?

[96] It is also the tenfold penalty described in the myth of Er that a man must pay for crimes during his life of a hundred years (cf. n. 83 above).

[97] See Ficino's Phaedrus Commentary, summa 25 (ed. Allen, pp. 170–171). See my Platonism , pp. 177–178.

[98] "Myriad" indeed can mean a huge crowd—the emotional and not just the numerical ten thousand.


77

gue, in three "secret" ways: as 1002 ; as the number that contains 100 diagonal powers; and as the principal factor of a million. Moreover, it has an "unequal dignity" as 10x1000 (10x103 ) but an equal dignity as 100x100 (102 x102 ). As the latter it is "the century of centuries," and through it "not only republics but all ages may be measured" (15.52–53). It is thus the number signifying the absolute temporal measure of the spans of all "compounded" things viewed in their species and kinds, while its constituent roots of 100 and 10 serve by implication as measures of the lesser spans, the centuries and decades, apportioned to individual entities (15.53–55).

ii. Ficino next turns to the second "hidden part" of 1728, namely to the 700. This was much more difficult to extract from Plato's conundrum than the 1000, and he was forced to delve more deeply into the series of cruces at 546C which declares that two harmonies result from the coupling of a base of four thirds to a root of 5 at the third augmentation, the one being "the product of equal factors and of a hundred multiplied the same number of times," the other being "of equal length but very oblong." This latter is enigmatically described by Plato as the 100 "of numbers from comparable diagonals of the 5, with individual diagonals requiring one, but those which are not comparable requiring two."[99] Since the text immediately goes on to mention that "the 100 of the cubes is of the three," Ficino interprets it to mean that, as will be the case with the myriad, Plato is presenting us with the 100 thrice, the 100 being the second in the "order" of universal numbers stemming from the 10, but the first equilateral, the first power, in that order (14.16–18). We recall that it is the 100 which is celebrated, again appropriately, in book 10 of the Republic at 615AB in the climactic account of the myth of Er, a hundred years being reckoned there as we have seen as the ideal length of a man's life. Clearly the 100 as a century—the basic unit of an age—is the governing paradigm, for the 100 is described as the "brood" or "fruit" of the 10 (15.13–14), and hence as the brood of the temporal decade, the leading of the decad—and thus of the tetraktys—to itself.

Plato's opening phrase at 546C3 describes the first harmony as


78

"equally equal," as 100x100. This Ficino calls "the first denomination," and he takes it to be referring to the 100, itself an equilateral, as the root and therefore as the "producer" of the ampler equilateral of the 10,000, which as 102 x102 is "equally equal," the square of a square as we have seen.

Plato's second harmony is "of equal length" with the first and must therefore be for Ficino 100 long. But its "width" is measured by a number that is the diagonal of a square with sides of 5—Ficino's interpretation of the phrase "of the pempad." The irrational diagonal of such a square is the square root of twice the square of its side, and therefore

figure
50. But the rational diagonal is the square root of twice the square of the side minus 1, and therefore
figure
49. In other words the rational root of the diagonal power of 50 is 7.[100] Thus with a length of 100 and a width of 7 Ficino arrives at the second component of the geometric number, namely at 700 (14.26–28). This he refers to as the "second denomination" of the 100, and he calls it the 100 "of innumerable planes" (15.31–32). He identifies it with the seven planets just as he identifies the 1000 with the eighth sphere, the firmament, of the fixed stars, an unequilateral number like 700 being appropriate for such wanderers (when compared with the even motion of the firmament) (14.40–41, 47–51; cf. 3.97–98).

Finally he refers to the "third denomination" of the 100 when it signifies the cube root of a million (14.35–38; 15.30–31), a million being the value he sees Plato having intended by the phrase at 546C6, "But the hundred of the cubes is of the three," "of the three" meaning raised to the third power (5.44–45). For, he observes, Plato had deliberately extended "the fatal numbers to the solid as to the highest [point or power], so that hence he might show, having reached the highest already, that little by little all are brought back to the opposite" (3.111–113). This million refers to all the heavenly bodies, seen and unseen in the firmament,[101] and beneath it is situated presumably the realm of the innumerable planes.

In short, Ficino interprets what he sees as Plato's triple reference here to 100 as follows: the 1002 refers to the 10,000 visible beings in the firmament (itself symbolized by the 1000); the 100x7 refers to the seven planets, the most obviously visible of heavenly beings beneath

[100] See n. 17 to Text 2, p. 167 below. There are many difficulties.

[101] For the theory of countless "unseen" beings in the heavens, which has good Ptolemaic authority, see Chapter 4 below.


79

the firmament; and the 1003 refers to the 1,000,000 of the totality of the heavenly beings unseen as well as seen.

iii. The final hidden part of 1728 is 28. If 1000 and 10,000 betoken the firmament and the visible stars, and 700 beto-kens the seven planets, then 28 must betoken the Moon specifically (3.98, 103; 14.41). For, apart from being the number of days in the lunar month and of her mansions, 28 is 7x4, that is, the number of the planets times the number of the elements. It is thus a singularly appropriate product to symbolize the planet that mediates between the planetary and the elemental spheres. As the seventh and nearest planet—and Ficino says that 6 betokens the six higher planets (3.105)—the Moon has no harmony or proportion with the firmament except by way of the six higher planets, which have "a similar proportion to the stars as the Moon to them" (14.41–45). What Ficino surely has in mind here is not some numerical proportion[102] but rather the fact that 28 is the second perfect number after 6, and as such "brings the second perfection to things subject to fate," that is, to sublunar generation (3.106–107).[103] Once again this raises the possibility that the second perfection must depend in some way on the first, just as 12, the cube root of the fatal geometric number and the second spousal number, also depends on 6, the first spousal that had constituted Plato's "exordium." At all events, as 4x7, an oblong number that is also the sum of its parts and therefore a perfect number, 28 is particularly appropriate for the Moon and her mansions and for the power she exercises over all beneath her sway.

D. To conclude, the fatal number had as its hidden parts the three numbers associated with the firmament, with the planets and with the Moon, even as its most prominent "unhidden" part, its cube root, its trinitarian root if you will, constituted the number of abundance, and thus the number associated with the months, with the zodiacal signs, with the Olympian deities, with the books of Plato's Laws and the books of Vergil's prophetic Aeneid , with the tribes of Israel, with Christ's Apostles, with the gates of the Apocalypse's New Jerusalem,

[103] In what does this "second perfection" consist?


80

and so forth.[104] It was thus a cornucopia enveloped in the same kind of mystery that had long enveloped the Pythagoreans' tetraktys. Indeed, from a musical viewpoint the mystery was the very same in that the fatal number and its cube root also contained the three universal harmonies,[105] as Ficino himself had already pointed out in his epitome for the Epinomis .[106] Finally, whatever the remaining cruces in Plato's crux laden description of the number, 1728 was in wonderful accord both with Aristotle's gloss and with the cosmological numerology of Plato's Timaeus .

Nonetheless, the origins of 1728 and its cube root lie, Ficino was convinced, in the perfect number 6, and clearly not in the quotidian 5. For Plato had intended us to look beyond the realm of Fate that 12 signifies to the higher realm of Providence; and to set another, a hexadic, time, God's time, over and against both the decades, the centuries, and the millennia that we measure by 10 and its multiples, and the dodecadic time of the Sun, the Moon, and the stars, and the calendars we base upon them. He had intended us, that is, to set a perfect, golden time over and against both the iron time, the clock time, of nature's and of man's present imperfection and mutability, and the silver time of the celestial spheres. However, the poets' superficially simple and nostalgic notion of a "golden" time and its generation or regeneration has complex, far-reaching mythological and philosophical implications for the Neoplatonic tradition that Ficino inherited and revived, and to some of these we must now turn.

[104] As the reference in the De Numero Fatali 12 indicates, 144 as the square of 12 was also in Ficino's mind as signifying a time when "a great permutation occurs among men." We recall that 144,000 is the number of the saved in Revelation 7:4–8.

[105] Bowen, "Ficino's Analysis of Musical Harmonia ," pp. 21–23, points out that the two scales described by Ficino, the Pythagorean and the syntonic diatonic, both derive from the tetraktys. See also Heninger, Touches of Sweet Harmony , pp. 93–97.

[106] See Chapter 1, p. 29 above.


81

3
Eugenics, the Habitus , and the Spirit

"Iam redit et Virgo, redeunt Saturnia regna"


In the next two chapters I will explore several interrelated mythological and historical themes that Ficino raised in the De Numero Fatali . In the process I shall be plowing some fresh ground in our understanding of his philosophy and entertaining speculative possibilities that scholars may wish to refine or challenge, or at least to measure against other texts more familiar to them. Throughout we should bear in mind that this commentary was one of Ficino's last scholarly enterprises, and certainly his last Plato commentary; and it was undertaken under the influence of planetary configurations quite different from those that had marked out 1484 as a year propitious for the course of the Platonic revival, which this commentary, along with the other commentaries that preceded it, was intended to expedite and serve.[1] Nevertheless, as an instauratory text, it is itself concerned

[1] 1484 was the year of the publication of Ficino's Platonis Opera Omnia . As Donald Weinstein observes in his Savonarola and Florence: Prophecy and Patriotism in the Renaissance (Princeton, 1970), it was also "a key year in much of the apocalyptic speculation of the time, . . . the annus mirabilis of contemporary prophetic speculation about religious change. Astrologi, profeti, uomini dotti e santi as well as men of lesser degrees of holiness were predicting for that year some great turning point in the history of Christianity, indeed in the religious history of the world" (pp. 75, 88). Indeed Eugenio Garin, Lo zodiaco , p. 86, speaks of the 1480s themselves as a decade "satura di profetismo ermetico, di annunzi escatologici de eversione o de adventu Antichristi ." In his Prognostica ad Viginti Annos Duratura of 1484, Paul of Middelburg, the astrologer

bishop of Fossombrone and Ficino's friend and correspondent, calculated on the basis of his reading of the ninth-century Arab Albumasar that the year 1484 would see a conjunction of Saturn and Jupiter that heralded mighty changes in the Christian religion (Weinstein, Savonarola , pp. 87–88, 89, notes that his calculations were taken over by Johannes Lichtenberger, court astrologer to the Emperor Frederick III, who in 1488 heralded the coming of a second Charlemagne to purify the Church). Cristoforo Landino, another of Ficino's friends, predicted on the basis of the same conjunction the return in 1484 of the veltro of Dante's Inferno 1.101–111 to inaugurate religious reform. The Hermetic prophet Giovanni Mercurio da Correggio chose 1484 as the year to appear on Palm Sunday in Rome and later on the Florentine streets calling for repentance before the coming millennium and proclaiming the advent of a new world religion (see Weinstein, Savonarola , pp. 199–202). And a contemporary dialogue entitled Trialogus in Rebus Futuris XX Annorum Proximorum and attributed to Lodovicus Rigius (Cornarius)—see Martin C. Davies, "An Enigma and a Phantom: Giovanni Aretino and Giacomo Languschi," Humanistica Lovaniensia 37 (1988), 1–29 at 17–21—calculated that a conjunction of Jupiter and Saturn would occur between 1484 and 1504 and that this would announce the end of the world and the coming of Antichrist. See too Pico's Disputationes adversus Astrologiam Divinatricem 5 passim (ed. Eugenio Garin, 2 vols. [Florence, 1946–1952], 1:520–623, with bibliography and notes on pp. 635–639 and 667–669). In the event, it turned out to be the year of the death of Pope Sixtus IV.

Both Sebastiano Gentile, in his edition of the first book of Ficino's Epistulae , pp. xxxvi–xlii, and James Hankins, in his Plato in the Italian Renaissance 1:302–304, have recently called our attention to the role of "astrological considerations" in general in Ficino's career. Hankins cites the astrological significance Ficino assigned to the publication date of his Plotinus translation (Opera , p. 1537), and also his reply to Janus Pannonius (Opera , pp. 871–872). He concludes—and Gentile concurs—that, in view of the evidence, "it is difficult to believe that the appearance of Ficino's Platonis opera omnia in the Great Year 1484 was not related to Ficino's millennial hopes for a renewal of Christianity through the pia philosophia of Platonism" (p. 304). He observes, moreover, that for Ficino the "conjunction of Saturn and Jupiter signified the conjoining of wisdom and power, the precondition for a Golden Age," and refers to Ficino's argumentum for Plato's Second Letter : "Wisdom which remains distant from power is lame. The great conjunctions of the planets teach us this. Jupiter is the lord; Saturn the philosopher. Surely, unless these be conjoined nothing either great or stable may be established" (his trans., p. 304). On the other hand, Ficino devotes chapter 4 of his De Christiana Religione of 1473–1474 (Opera , pp. 12–13) to refuting the idea that the laws of Christianity could be influenced by the stars.


82

with an instauration that Ficino still saw in the mid 1490s as imminent: the generation and the birth of a Florentine Platonism that would restore the fabled golden age and reunite religion with philosophy, Themis with Pallas.[2] In that hallowed time both goddesses would exercise a sovereign, a jovian sway over the just state, its wise ruler or rulers in their nocturnal council, and its tempered offspring. But what goes to the generation of such offspring? What are the factors that the guardians of the ideally constituted republic must always take into

[2] See Ficino's prologue to his De Christiana Religione (Opera , p. 1), where he mourns the lot of the present iron age and the separation of Pallas from Themis, that is, of wisdom from integrity (honestas ). Cf. Ficino's letter to Giovanni Francesco Ippoliti

in the fourth book of his Epistulae (Opera , pp. 761.3–763; trans. in Letters , 3:28–31 [no. 18]), which declares that the golden age will return "only when power and wisdom come together in the same mind," and the ruler is a philosopher. Cf. also his speech in praise of philosophy in the same book (Opera , pp. 757.3–759; trans. in Letters 3:18–21 [no. 13]), which asserts that "there was once a golden age when wisdom reigned, and that if ever philosophy reigns again the golden age will return." In general see Hankins, Plato , pp. 284–297.


83

consideration if they wish to preserve it as long as possible from internal dissolution? What kind of magic must they call upon when they ordain the day and the hour for its citizens to marry and to breed?[3]

Plato's radical views on eugenics are principally set forth in two dialogues: in the Republic 5.458C ff. and in the Laws 6.772D ff. and 783D ff. Ficino's argumenta for both these discussions, however, are summary in nature and turn aside to other issues;[4] and the theme of best breeding only comes to the forefront of his mind much later, in the course of writing the thirteenth chapter of his De Numero Fatali . Even then, as we might anticipate, it occurs in the context of the accompanying mathematical speculations bearing their own burden of interpretative challenges.

Ficino undertakes to expound what he regards as the Pythagorean and Platonic view of eugenics with its basis in the musical theory of proportions. Good offspring require both parents to be good, while bad offspring issue from a union between two bad parents, and mixed offspring from a union between a good and a bad parent. If this sounds too simple and schematic, we should recall that elsewhere, notably in the De Vita , Ficino expatiates on the many ways a scholar particularly can set about overcoming hereditary traits and harnessing a bad remperament—what we would now think of as a bed set of genes—to a rational pursuit of the true and the good. Indeed, for all its medical and psychological preoccupations with pathological moods of melancholy, lassitude, and compulsion, and for all its astrological concerns with environmental and stellar conditioning, the De Vita is remarkably optimistic about the possibilities of establishing personal autonomy, about elective as well as predictive astrology;[5] and about achieving a

[3] The magus operates by way of reconciling or exploiting the attractions and repulsions of nature, and the breeder does the same in a way with regard to stock. The breeder is therefore a kind of magus, and Plato's magistrate is among other things a breeder. For Ficino the implication that he is therefore a magus would not be wholly fanciful.

[4] Opera , pp. 1404–1406, 1503–1505.

[5] Kaske in her "Introduction" to Marsilio Ficino: Three Books on Life , ed. and trans. Kaske and Clark, p. 37, defines elective or catarchic astrology as "a matter of timing one's activities to coincide with the predicted dominance of favorable stars, of availing

oneself of general, already-existing forces, much as one does when launching a ship with the ebbing of the tide." Predictive astrology, by contrast, is keyed either to the casting of nativities (genethliacal astrology) or to the establishment of the horoscope of any particular moment in order to seek answers "to specific personal questions (called 'interrogations' or 'judgements') in the position of the stars at the time of asking" (interrogatory or horary astrology). For the distinctions and for an account of the deep tension in the humanists between their belief in human autonomy and their sense of a rebirth governed by the movements of the stars, see Garin, Lo zodiaco , chapter 2.


84

degree of choice even over biological and psychological matters usually subordinated to forces—natural, daemonic, planetary, and zodiacal—outside our normal control. Ficino compiled it so that readers could prolong and improve their lives, though this is hardly the impression one gets from the pertinent sections of the monumental study by Panofsky, Saxl, and Klibansky, Saturn and Melancholy , which overstate the case for Ficino's melancholy by ignoring his wit, his playfulness, and the fundamental optimism of his philosophical premises.[6] Clearly, we are off to a much better temperamental (and therefore philosophical) start if we were begotten by good parents; but Ficino never supposed that inherited characteristics are unassailably determinative of our intellectual and spiritual lives, since he was a believer, as we shall see, in disciplina and in the notion of free will or at least of free choice (arbitrium ) which undergirds it.[7]

[6] This was first published by Erwin Panofsky and Fritz Saxl as Dürers "Melencolia I": Eine quellen- und typengeschichtliche Untersuchung (Leipzig and Berlin, 1923) and then revised with the help of Raymond Klibansky as Saturn and Melancholy (London and New York, 1964); see especially chapter 2, pp. 241–274, with my criticisms in Platonism , pp. 93–94, 192–194, esp. 194 nn. 29, 31. See also Panofsky's The Life and Art of Albrecht Dürer , 4th ed. (Princeton, 1955), pp. 165–171; Paul Oskar Kristeller, The Philosophy of Marsilio Ficino (New York, 1943), pp. 208–214; and André Chastel, Marsile Ficin et l'art (Geneva and Lille, 1954), pp. 163–171. Eugenio Garin too has drawn an attractive but unwarrantably gloomy portrait of Ficino in "Immagini e simboli in Marsilio Ficino," in his Medioevo e Rinascimento (Bari, 1954; 2d ed., 1961), pp. 288–310. The essay has been translated by Victor A. Velen and Elizabeth Velen in Eugenio Garin, Portraits from the Quattrocento (New York, 1972), pp. 142–160.

See the exchange of letters in 1476 between Ficino and Cavalcanti now in Ficino's third book of Epistulae (Opera , pp. 732–733; trans. in Letters 2:31–34 [nos. 23 and 24]). Burdened with a horoscope where Saturn was almost in the midst of his ascendant sign of Aquarius, where Mars was situated too, Ficino wittily acknowledges his melancholy disposition and says he has to temper it frequently by singing to his lyre. He concludes that a saturnian nature might be "a unique and divine gift" as Aristotle had argued in the Problemata 30.953a. Note that the lyre, presumably the apollonian lyre, is what makes saturnian influence tolerable; for other antidotes see his De Vita 1.10. Corsi had claimed in his Vita Ficini 15 (ed. Marcel in his Marsile Ficin , pp. 685–686; trans. in Letters 3:143) that, though Ficino was publicly cheerful, festive, and witty, his friends suspected he sat long in solitude numb with melancholy. Corsi also states that Ficino shunned all casters of horoscopes, along with disputatious Scholastics, as if they were dogs and snakes (ibid. 19).

[7] As Kaske points out in her "Introduction," pp. 57–59.


85

Numbers themselves, from the Pythagorean standpoint, are marriage partners. To begin, Ficino states simply that the odd numbers are male, and hence bridegrooms and fathers, because of the strength and vigor in "their middle knot, the one"; and that even numbers are female, and hence brides and mothers.[8] But this simple view entails endless contradictions, as we shall see. For to argue that all mothers must be evens and at the same time that all evens are bad voids the possibility of there ever being a good child, even in the equilateral series. Thus Ficino goes on to say that gender subordination must also pertain within these categories in that a more outstanding (a higher?) even number should be thought of as the groom for an inferior (a lower?) even bride; and similarly with odd numbers. This must be the key to what would otherwise be a baffling observation; for chapter 13 goes on to declare that the equilaterals—that is, 4, 9, 16, 25, 36, and so on—are the filii of good parents; that the unequilaterals—that is, 6, 12, 20, 30, 42, and so on—are the filii of bad; and that the trigons—that is, 3, 6, 10, 15, 21, and so on—are the filii of mixed parents. Now filii here must mean "children," not just "sons," since half of the equilaterals and trigons and all of the unequilaterals are even and therefore female. Moreover, the basic spousal union is conceived of as multiplication between adjacent numbers—2x3, 3x4, 4x5, and so forth—and thus as a union between male and female. But such a union produces not the equilateral but the unequilateral series, though the subsequent multiplication of adjacent equilaterals, being male and female, could obviously be seen as a union that produces good offspring, but only insofar as it produces equilaterals (though they will always be even and therefore female!)—for instance, 4x9=36. Furthermore, the unequilaterals, at least the long ones that are Ficino's sole concern, being entirely male, could not be said to beget together, unless, that is, we adopt his second category, namely that a higher number in any one series is the groom for a lower one in the same series.[9] The same pertains mutatis mutandis for the trigons.

Nevertheless, for Ficino composite numbers are produced by addition as well as by multiplication. Thus, when he declares that the equi-

[8] Cf. Plato, Laws 4.717AB: the gods below "should receive everything in even numbers, and of the second choice, and ill omen, while the odd numbers, and the first choice, and the things of lucky omen, are given to the gods above." Cf. Proclus, Platonic Theology 4.29 (ed. and trans. H. D. Saffrey and L. G. Westerink, 5 vols. to date [Paris, 1968–], 4:86.19–87.4); and Ficino's Commentary on St. Paul 10 (Opera , p. 445): "Numero Deus impari gaudet, id est, ternario."

[9] Ficino does not say that they have to be adjacent, but again remote liaisons are of little or no interest to him, or to the arithmological tradition.


86

laterals are the children of good parents, he cannot mean that they are the products of 2x2, 3x3, 4x4, 5x5, and so on; for such would be homoerotic or autoerotic unions, and marriages in the Platonic commonwealth are strictly heterosexual, being designed to produce children for the state. Rather, he must mean that the equilaterals spring from the addition of (presumably adjacent) numbers in the equilateral series—4, for instance, is the child of 1+3, 9 the child of 4+5.[10] Similarly, the unequilaterals must be the children of bad parents insofar as they spring from the addition of (presumably adjacent) numbers in the unequilateral series—6, for instance, is the child of 2+4. Again, a similar situation pertains for the trigons.

In short, Ficino is not thinking here of the offspring of the spousal series, that is, of products resulting from the multiplication of adjacent odd and even numbers in the regular series of numbers, though initially this is what we might be led to expect; for such spousal unions produce the "bad" unequilaterals as we have seen. Rather, he has in mind offspring that are the sums in the various addition series and notably in the equilateral, unequilateral, and trigon series. However, it is from additions in the equilateral series alone, a series in which each parent possesses "an equal and right complexion" and a unitary power, that children proceed who are "indissoluble, strong, well-ordered, and fertile."[11]

The fatal "geometric" or "proportional" number is "universal," Ficino declares, since it embraces many kinds of number—odd and even, equilateral and unequilateral, square and oblong, plane and solid, lateral and diagonal—as well as the better harmony (i.e., diapente) and the worse (i.e., diatessaron). Hence it contains within itself "an immense," that is, a universal, "power" to produce both good and bad progeny. It triples, if you will, the ambivalent power of the 12; and as a "discordant concord" it presides alike over birth and death, over benign opportunities and malign occasions. Hence its existence considerably complicates the apparent simplicity of Ficino's injunction

[10] We cannot press the logic of this too curiously, for the resulting sums of the lower numbers soon become greater than the higher numbers in the series to which they are added; e.g., 9 (as the sum of 1+3+5) is greater than 7, the next addend.

[11] Presumably, Ficino would consider unions between nonadjacent numbers in any addition series either illegitimate or sterile unions, and a fortiori those between numbers in different series, though the notion of sterility has a paradoxical cast to it in this mathematical context. Again, we must guard against pushing the logic of Ficino's analogies too far, or taking a passing remark as a principle; and we must also recall that numbers can be members of more than one series.


87

at the end of chapter 13 to mark the "praiseworthy" and "unpraiseworthy" numbers in the life spans of men, and in the larger spans of nature and the world, in order to seize the moments most opportune for fertility or to shun those most vulnerable to evil and sterility. He clearly envisages a subtle play between the role of such numbers in individual lives and their role in the often longer, sometimes immeasurably longer, destinies of groups, of societies, of peoples—their role, that is, in personal and impersonal, and in national and natural history. In either event the antithetical notions of fertility and sterility apply to every kind of sublunar activity: to the begetting of artistic, moral, intellectual, and spiritual, as well as physical, offspring by men, by political and other social entities, by nature, by time itself.

In addressing the specific issue of physical procreation and the group marriages to be orchestrated and not just arranged by the state's magistrates, Ficino sees Plato as prescribing three things: first, an "equable air"—presumably not just in the sense of climate or season generally, but in the specific sense that the air must be perfectly tempered in its mixture of humidity and heat;[12] second, a "solid" disposition or habitus , the result of the right temperament and the right age; and third, an astrologically favorable arrangement in the heavens of the Sun, Venus, Jupiter, and the Moon—the life-giving planets.[13] As a general rule, moreover, the less powerful families in the state should be married into the more powerful in order that marriage might serve as the vital leveler and conditioner of a commonwealth.[14]

The Republic 's book 5.454–463, and especially 458D and 460E, had established as the optimum time for men to beget children the

[12] Ficino frequently refers in his Epistulae to the temperate air of particular places, particularly at Careggi (his retreat on Monte Vecchio) and at Fiesole; see, for instance, Opera , pp. 843.4 (on Careggi and the reconciling of Apollo with saturnian Pan), 844.2 (on Monte Vecchio), 893.2.

[13] It would be interesting to discover whether Ficino linked this in his mind with any particular Florentine marriage or set of marriages. His letter in praise of marriage to Antonio Pelotti in the fourth book of his Epistulae (Opera , pp. 778.3–779; trans. in Letters 3:69–71 [no. 34]) stresses the parallels between governing the domestic and governing the greater republic, though it says nothing about Pelotti's wedding itself; and the famous letter to Lorenzo di Pierfrancesco, now in the fifth book of his Epistulae (Opera , pp. 805.2–806; trans. in Letters 4:61–63 [no. 46]), speaks of Lorenzo marrying the nymph humanitas . We might bear in mind that this letter has been adduced as a likely source for the program of Botticelli's masterpiece, the Primavera , recommissioned, apparently, for Lorenzo's wedding to Semiramide Appiani in 1482.

[14] Given the tripartite model for the soul, does Ficino see Plato as advocating the leveling of the irascible power by means of the concupiscible? Or is it rather a question of modulating differing aspects within the irascible power itself?


88

span between thirty and fifty-five, and for women that between twenty and forty, intervals of twenty-five and twenty years respectively, the first being an equilateral, the second an unequilateral number. But in uniting the right parents together, Ficino argues in chapter 16, the magistrates must do more than check the birth dates of the mating partners; they must ensure that both parents' ingenia are good, and not so much equal as proportionate to each other. He invokes both the Statesman and the Laws 6.772DE (where Plato argues for an earlier age for men to begin procreation, namely twenty-five) in order to gloss the notion that there is an ideal eugenic mixture of gentler temperaments with the more vehement, and that this ensures the procreation of offspring who are neither cowardly nor ferocious.[15]

Of especial interest in this context is the term ingenium , which can be variously rendered as character, mood, temperament, nature, bent, inclination, disposition, natural abilities, talent, wit, ingenuity, skill. It and its cognates such as ingeniosus and ingeniatus are etymologically related to the word gignere meaning "to beget or create" and to the word genius meaning the attendant daemon or spirit that in Latin folklore watches over our begetting and birth and thereafter over our physical fortune and our eventual death. In the Christian West the daemon-genius became seen too as the guardian over our destiny as an intellectual and spiritual being, until it became equated eventually with our inmost potential, our unique gifts. Geniuses or daemons were even thought to preside over the destinies of places, peoples, movements, and institutions.[16]Ingenium , in other words, is linked

[15] But at 785B Plato goes on to declare that the span of marriageable years for a woman should be 16 or 20 and for a man 30 or 35. This implies that a considerable difference in age between partners does not in itself render their union untempered.

[16] Of particular importance for Ficino were Plato's several references to Socrates' "warning voice," his daimonion (in the Alcibiades I 103A, 105E, 124C, Apology 31C, 40A, Euthydemus 273A, Euthyphro 3B, Phaedrus 242C, Republic 6.496C, Theages 128D, etc.); his great myths of the guardian daemons in the Phaedo 107DE and in the Republic 617DE and 620DE; his definition in the Symposium 202DE that "every daimonion is midway between a god and a mortal"; and his refusal to accept in the Laws 905D–907D that gods or daemons can be influenced by spells or rituals. Of singular importance too were: Plotinus's treatise on the personal daemon, the Enneads 3.4; the treatise on Platonic daemonology by Apuleius, De Deo Socratis , and that by Plutarch, De Genio Socratis ; Porphyry's De Abstinentia 2; the daemonological sections in Calcidius's In Timaeum , in Iamblichus's De Mysteriis , and, in a hostile context, in Augustine's Civitas Dei ; and the work of Proclus in its entirety. See D. P. Walker, Spiritual and Demonic Magic: From Ficino to Campanella (London, 1958), pp. 3–29, 44–53; Maurice de Gandillac, "Astres, anges et génies chez Marsile Ficin," in Umanesimo e esoter-

ismo: Atti del V convegno internazionale di studi umanistici , ed. Enrico Castelli (Padua, 1960), pp. 85–119; also my Platonism , chapter 1; and "Summoning Plotinus: Ficino, Smoke, and the Strangled Chickens," In Reconsidering the Renaissance: Papers from the 1987 CEMERS Conference , ed. Mario A. Di Cesare (Binghamton, 1992), pp. 63–88.


89

from the beginning with the notion of the natural capacities given a person from birth; the innate bent, disposition, and acuity of a thinking individual. Ficino seems to be using it here also to signify what is then passed on to children—the physical, temperamental, and above all mental powers of the father, and secondarily of the mother, that make for balance and therefore fertility, success, and eudaimonia —inner harmony. Given Ficino's Platonic assumptions, the term is linked to the ability and will to acquire knowledge and wisdom; and given his astrological assumptions, he thinks of it as governed in part at least by starry influences, or more questionably by various daemons in the celestial spheres following in the trains of their planetary gods.[17]

Ingenium seems, furthermore, to be closely linked with the notion of the habitus , from which indeed we and the monks get the word "habit," and which is etymologically linked to the verb habere , "to have." Habitus too can be rendered in English as "character" and "condition," though its range of meanings is quite different from that of ingenium , and it cannot be used to signify the interdependent notions of skill, talent, wit, and ingenuity. For the Schoolmen it became the standard equivalent for the Greek hexis and was therefore linked antithetically with actus , the Greek energeia .[18] For Ficino's deployment of this difficult technical term, however, let us turn to his magnum opus, the eighteen-book Platonic Theology .[19] The habitus can refer, he says, to the natural optimum condition of the body, the goal,

[17] In the lexicon Ficino copied out during the 1450s as a tool for learning Greek and now preserved in the Laurenziana's MS Ashb. 1439—see Gentile in Mostra , pp. 23–25 (no. 19)—he merely glosses ingenium along with natura at f. 88r as the equivalent for physis . But this clearly does not conform to his normal usage where ingenium connotes talent, wit, ingenuity, mental acuity. The lexicon has been edited by Rosario Pintaudi as Marsilio Ficino: Lessico Greco- Latino: Laur. Ashb. 1439 (Rome, 1977), where the reference appears on p. 131 (LXIII.16).

[18] See my Icastes: Marsilio Ficino's Interpretation of Plato's "Sophist" (Berkeley, Los Angeles, Oxford, 1989), pp. 137 ff. May I take this opportunity to note some corrections and an addition: p. 12.13 "wiser"; p. 116.19 "which bend"; p. 133.22 "within our minds"; p. 143.3 "nature, while"; p. 149 n. 50.3up "the creative power, the mother of the good things that pertain to"; p. 214.14 "f.62r"; p. 307 col. 1.6up "Icastes" should be a new entry.

For Zeus as a sophist at p. 96.12 ff., cf. Ps.-Plato, Minos 319C (which Ficino considered authentic), and Proclus, In Timaeum 2 (ed. Diehl, 1:316.2–3).

[19] See the index notabilium in Marcel's edition.


90

if you will, of medicine;[20] and as such it can be said "to pass into" or "to take over" our nature or to become as it were a second nature that moves us while remaining immobile itself.[21] It can also "play the part of" or "do duty for" our "natural form."[22] The soul itself, even when separated from the body, has a habitus by which it is moved.[23] Ficino believes of course that the soul only (re)acquires its true habitus when it has returned to its "head," that is, to its "intelligence" (mens ).[24] Indeed, the acquisition of such a habitus becomes man's primary goal, since it contains the soul's formulae idearum which when led forth (eductae ) into act enable the soul to rise from the sensible to the intelligible, and to be joined with the Ideas.[25] For the true habitus contains the species or Ideas as they are present in us,[26] the species indeed that correspond to all things that exist in the world in act.[27] Moreover, because all such forms and species do exist in the world in act, we must postulate a universal habitus , a habitus for the world.[28] Interestingly, the antithetical relationship with actus enables Ficino on some occasions to use habitus as a synonym for potentiality (though strictly speaking it signifies one kind of potentiality: that which is acquired). Hence he can argue that, whereas individual human beings

[20] Platonic Theology 11.5 (ed. Marcel, 2:129): "Complexio quoque plantarum et animalium quam mirabili medicinae artis solertia utitur in conservando habitu naturali aut recuperando" (Marcel renders habitu here as "équilibre").

[21] Ibid. 15.18 (ed. Marcel, 3:98): "habitus, qui transit in subiecti naturam, immo subiecti naturam usurpat ipse sibi, certam praestat proclivitatem et subiectum movet immobilis."

[22] Ibid. 15.19 (ed. Marcel, 3:103): "habitus non imaginarium quiddam est, sed naturalis formae gerit vicem."

[23] Ibid. 18.8 (ed. Marcel, 3:200): "Ita enim animus habitu movetur et agit, sicut natura formis. . . . Remanere vero in anima separata habitus tum morum tum disciplinarum tam bonos quam malos . . . dicitur habitum ita in naturam converti."

[24] Ibid. 16.7 (ed. Marcel, 3:134–135): "motus et habitus animae, quatenus intellectualis rationalisque est, circuitus esse debeat . . . cum primum animus in caput suum, id est mentem, erectus, in habitum suum prorsus restituetur."

[25] Ibid. 12.1 (ed. Marcel, 2:154): "Igitur mens per formulam suam ex habitu eductam in actum ideae divinae quadam praeparatione subnectitur."

[26] Ibid. 15.16 (ed. Marcel, 3:83–4); "habitum reformandi, . . . respondebimus vim mentis eamdem, quae et contrahit et servat habitum in eius naturam iam pene conversum, contrahere in intima sua speciem atque servare. Siquidem habitus fundatur in speciebus, species in habitu concluduntur. Proinde si habitus fit a mente, specie atque actu, ab aliquo istorum stabilitatem suam nanciscitur. . . . A specie igitur."

[27] Ibid. 13.2 (ed. Marcel, 2:210): "Mens autem . . . habitu quodam et, ut vult Plotinus, actu simul continet omnia."

[28] Ibid. 15.18 (ed. Marcel, 3:97): "si modo actus intelligendi dispositio est ad habitum, et ubi fit dispositio, ibi fit forma, id est habitus, habitus universalis ex universalibus actibus atque formis [est]."


91

possess all the arts secundum habitum , yet different arts are practiced by different individuals secundum actum ; but in the angel all the arts are united habitu atque actu .[29] On other occasions, however, he finds it useful to preserve the distinction between one's innate potentia and one's acquired or nurtured habitus .[30] What makes for the acquisition of a perfect habitus , whether of the body, the soul, the human mind, or the angelic mind, is both praeparatio and affectio .[31] The habitus is thus tied conceptually both to the notion of form—the habitus being the condition of ourselves or of some part of ourselves which most nearly approximates to the perfection of our form—and to the notion of power, the power that we have been born with but have nurtured by praeparatio and by what the De Numero Fatali refers to alternatively as disciplina . As the fifth reference (that from 16.7) suggests, we can even think of it as the potentiality in our soul for becoming pure mind in the actuality of its perfect circular motion, the motion-in-rest of contemplation. Immobile itself, it nevertheless provides the soul with the "proclivity" for the absolute motion that is its blessed, its eternal life.

In the De Numero Fatali Ficino mentions the habitus in chapters 2.8–9, 3.113–115, and 16.1 (title), 21–25.[32] His most important observation, however, occurs in chapter 12.49–51: "as long as all proportions and harmonies of this kind prevail among mankind, then a good habitus endures in bodies, spirits, souls, and states." In other words, the object of the philosopher-guardians is to ensure by way of their determination of breeding times that the republic's citizens are endowed with a good habitus in their bodies, spirits, and souls, the assumption being that we need to achieve this optimum condition at all three levels simultaneously.[33] If this threefold goal is achieved, then

[29] Ibid.: "Artes igitur dividantur oportet in hominum specie secundum actum, quia alii alias meditentur, non tamen secundum habitum, quia singuli cunctas possideant. Siquidem in angelo quolibet uniuntur cunctae habitu atque actu."

[30] E.g., at 14.3 (ed. Marcel, 2:258).

[31] Ibid. 14.6 (ed. Marcel, 2:268): "Nam praeparatio sive affectio formam habitumque respicit, atque certa quaedam affectio certum habitum"; and again 15.19 (ed. Marcel, 3:102): "praeparationes, quantum ad certos habitus conferunt atque cum illis proportione aliqua congruunt, tantum habitus diversos impediunt."

[32] "when number reaches six, which is perfect, it designates the perfect habit" (2.8–9); "For the condition of mobile nature does not suffer it to remain for a long time in the same or in a similar habit" (3.113–115); "concerning the body's habit" (16.1); "even habits are generated from odd numbers . . . but odd habits are generated from even numbers" (16.21–22); "the opportune time for public marriages requires evenness in the air and solidity in each body's habit, desire, and age" (16.23–25).

[33] This points to a holistic obsession in the Platonic tradition with the notion

of harmony binding every ontological level and thus of uniting a beautiful soul to a beautiful body. Set against it are the arguments of the Phaedo and the vivid example of the virtuous soul of Socrates trapped in a satyr's body.


92

the state itself will possess a good habitus , at least for its allotted time; for ultimately, observes chapter 3's concluding line, "the condition of mobile Nature does not suffer it to remain in the same or a similar habitus for any length of time."[34]

In arguing Platonically in chapter 16 that our "composed body" is a "discordant concord"—like, we recall, the geometric number—Ficino turns predictably to two analogies, a musical one and a mathematical one, for what endows it with concord, namely an even habitus . "Even habitus " are like the harmonies of different voices in a choir, he says, the different harmonies that unite in the diapason, and they are like the sums (and clearly not just the even sums which alternate with the odd) that are generated from the odd numbers in the equilateral addition series. "Odd habitus ," by contrast, are generated from even numbers, meaning from the even numbers in the unequilateral addition series (and not from the alternating even square numbers in the equilateral series).[35] Thus an even-tempered habitus is like any equilateral: as a sum it is the child of the odd numbers, but as a product it is the result of equality and balance, of a number having multiplied itself, raised itself to a higher power. It is the soul's inner concord, and when joined to the discordant body it creates the discordant concord of human harmony on earth.[36]

If the habitus is a kind of mathematical and specifically a geometrical power—indeed, in the Platonic Theology , as we have seen, Ficino treats it as the equivalent almost of our combined potentialities—then must we think of it as functioning like such a power, at least in particular contexts? In other words, does the habitus of the soul (and of its

[34] Interestingly, Ficino is now contrasting the permanent "condition" of "mobile Nature" with the transitory existence of a particular "habitus."

[35] The latter would only be possible if we conceived of odd habits arising from the addition of the even sum of the preceding odd numbers to the next odd number, as 25=16+9 where 16 is the sum of 1+3+5+7. But this recondite possibility cannot be what Ficino has in mind.

[36] Does Socrates' argument in the Phaedo that the soul itself is not a harmony prevent the habitus of the soul from being a harmony? And if so, is Ficino disregarding the Phaedo 's position at this point? Ficino addresses the discrepancy between the Phaedo 's claim that the soul is not a harmony and the Timaeus 's counter claim that it is in his Timaeus Commentary, chapter 28 (Opera , p. 1451.2). At 69B the Timaeus argues that the Demiurge created everything with harmonies; at 81E–82A and 86A–87C that there is a harmonious tempering of the elements in us; and at 87D–88C that soul and body must be harmoniously balanced together.


93

spirit and its body) work like the power, rational or irrational, of the hypotenuse of an isosceles right-angled triangle (or of the diagonal of a square constituted from two such triangles, which is the same thing); and is it therefore equal to double the square of either side (i.e., to the sum of the squares of both sides)? If so, we must entertain the possibility that the Pythagorean theorem has come to haunt the face of Ficino's faculty psychology. But what is the evidence that this is anything more than just an arresting image or a mere turn of phrase?

The traditional schema of the point progressing to the line to the plane to the solid goes back at least to the Pythagoreans and is repeated throughout antiquity and the Middle Ages.[37] Ficino turns to it on occasions to help define the serial subordination of the four hypostases in the Plotinian metaphysical system, the One, Mind, Soul, and Body;[38] and in doing so he often identifies the point with the One and the solid with Body—examples abound throughout his work. But he also identifies the line (and certainly the circular line) with Mind, and the plane with Soul.[39] While, to my knowledge, he nowhere advances all the elements of this series of analogies in one formal argument, he does introduce them dispersedly, and the schema obviously serves as one of his paradigms for metaphysical progression and hierarchical subordination. The implications for our understanding of the soul's internal structure and of its position on the Platonic scale of being in Ficino are extraordinary, I believe—though no scholar so far has ventured to entertain them.

Ficino's governing text here is the Timaeus 53C ff. on the role of

[37] Ficino was probably introduced to it in Aristotle: see, for example, the Topics 4.141b5–22 and Metaphysics 3.5.1001b26–1002b11.

[38] On Ficino's variations on this system, see Kristeller, Philosophy , pp. 106–108, 167–169, 266, 370, 384, 400–401; and my "Ficino's Theory of the Five Substances and the Neoplatonists' Parmenides ," Journal of Medieval and Renaissance Studies 12 (1982), 19–44, with further references. See also Tamara Albertini, "Marsilio Ficino: Das Problem der Vermittlung von Denken und Welt in einer Metaphysik der Einfachheit" (Diss. Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität, Munich, 1991).

[39] See, for instance, Ficino's letter to Lotterio Neroni, the penultimate letter in the third book of his Epistulae (Opera , p. 750.3; trans. in Letters 2:82–83 [no. 65]). Here he speaks of being either in "the undivided and motionless center" as in the one God, or in "the divided and mobile circumference" as in heaven and the elements, or in the "individual lines" that mediate between them, beginning at the center as undivided and motionless but gradually becoming divided and "mutable" as they approach the circumference. In these lines are the souls and minds. Cf. Pico della Mirandola, Conclusiones DCCCC, Conclusiones secundum Mathematicam Pythagorae , nos. 13 ("Quilibet numerus planus aequilaterus animam symbolizat") and 14 ("Quilibet numerus linearis symbolizat deos") in his Opera Omnia (Basel, 1572), p. 79.


94

triangles, duly bracketed by Timaeus himself as presenting views that are only "probable." Timaeus introduces the two kinds of right-angled triangles, the isosceles and the scalene (specifically the half-equilateral), that are the constituent parts of the regular solids constituting the four elements and the cosmos itself (to pan 55C4–6). At 69C ff. he goes on to describe the creation by the Demiurge's sons of the irrational soul and at 73B ff. their taking of the primary triangles (i.e., before their combination into the regular solids) to mix them in "due proportions" to make the marrow, which will serve as a "universal seed" and a vehicle for the soul. Ficino clearly rejoiced in some at least of the figural extensions (with the puns this term implies) of the Pythagorean mathematics which Timaeus is propounding in this, Plato's master dialogue on cosmology (second only in its overall authority to the dialogue named after another and even greater Pythagorean, Parmenides).[40] For in his own Timaeus Commentary he had explored the implications of this analysis and arrived at an interpretation that identified the soul itself as the exemplary triangle, its triple powers corresponding to the three angles and the three sides of the archetypal geometrical figure. At the end of chapter 28, having observed that "mathematicals accord with the soul, for we judge both of them to be midway between divine and natural things," Ficino proceeds as follows:

We use not only numbers to describe the soul but also [geometrical] figures so that we can think of it by way of the numbers as incorporeal but consider it by way of the figures as naturally declining towards bodies. The triangle accords with the soul; for just as the triangle from one angle extends to two more, so the soul, which flows out from an indivisible and divine substance, sinks into the entirely divisible nature of the body. If we compare the soul as it were to things divine, then it seems divided; for what the divine achieve through one unchanging power and in an instant, the soul achieves through many changing powers and actions and over intervals of time. But if we compare the soul to natural things, then we judge it to be indivisible. For it has no sundry parts as they have, separated here and there in place, but it is whole even in any one part of the whole; nor, as they do, does it pursue everything in motion and in time, but it attains something in a moment and pos-

[40] In his Timaeus Commentary 1 (Opera , p. 1438.2), Ficino followed Proclus (who followed Iamblichus) in linking the two dialogues and attributing Pythagorean speakers and a Pythagorean inspiration to them; see Proclus's In Timaeum 1 (ed. Diehl, 1:1.25 ff., 7.17 ff., 13.15–14.2, etc.). We might note that together they constituted the climactic second part of the Neoplatonists' two-part teaching cycle, for which see L. G. Westerink, Anonymous Prolegomena to Platonic Philosophy (Amsterdam, 1962), pp. xxxvii–xxxviii.


95

sesses it eternally. In this we can compare the soul, moreover, to the triangle, because the triangle is the first figure of those figures which consist of many lines and are led forth into extension (in rectum ). Similarly, the soul is the first of all to be divided up into many powers—powers that are subjected in it to the understanding—and it seems to be led forth into extension when it sinks from divinity down into nature. In this descent it flows out from the highest understanding down into three lower powers, that is, into discursive reasoning, into sense, and into the power of quickening, just as the triangle too, having been led forth from the point (signum ),[41] is drawn out into three angles. But I say the soul is the first in the genus of all to be mingled from many powers in a way, and to fall, so to speak, into extension (in rectum ). For above the soul the angelic mind requires no inferior powers within itself at all. The mind is pure and the mind is whole and sufficient; likewise it does not turn to inferiors, but it is turned back to divinity alone (from whence it exists) in the manner of a circle. And therefore its action is compared to a circle. For its action is one and equal, just as from a line that is one and equal comes the circle and with it a certain wonderful capacity for being both. Moreover, the circle is the first and last of the figures: first, because it has been enclosed by one line; last, because the figures constituted from the many lines, in that they submit to many faces [i.e., become polyhedra], to that extent they seem to approximate gradually to the circle's form as to their end. Similarly, the intellect too is the first of all to be created by God; and the intellectual countenance,[42] that is, the absolute order of things, is the last of all to blaze back in the mirror of nature, to which as to their end the natural forms gradually approach ever more closely.[43]

[41] Cf. Ficino's Timaeus Commentary 22 (Opera , p. 1449.3): "Quatuor apud mathematicum: signum, linea, planum atque profundum."

[42] With a play on the preceding reference to the "many faces" of polyhedra.

[43] Platonis Opera Omnia (1491), fol. 246v (sig. G[6]v) (i.e., Opera , pp. 1452–1453 [misnumbered 1450 and 1417]): "Congruunt animae mathematica, utraque enim inter divina et naturalia media iudicantur. Congruunt musici numeri animae plurimum, mobiles enim sunt; proptereaque animam quae est principium motionis rite significant. Non solum vero per numeros sed etiam per figuras describitur anima ut per numeros quidem incorporea cogitetur, per figuras autem cognoscatur ad corpora naturaliter declinare. Convenit triangulus animae. Quia sicut triangulus ab uno angulo in duos protenditur, sic anima ab individua divinaque substantia profluens in naturam corporis labitur penitus divisibilem. Ac si cum divinis conferatur, divisa videtur; quae enim illa per unam et stabilem virtutem agunt atque subito, haec per plures mutabilesque vires actionesque peragit ac temporis intervallis. Sin autem conferatur cum naturalibus, indivisa censetur; non enim alibi habet partes alias loco disiunctas ut illa [Op. alia], sed etiam [Op. est] in qualibet totius parte tota; neque omnia mobiliter temporeque persequitur sicut illa, sed nonnihil etiam subito [Op. subiecto] consequitur aeterneque possidet. Licet in hoc insuper animam cum triangulo comparare, quod triangulus prima figura est earum quae pluribus constantes lineis producuntur in rectum; anima similiter prima omnium in plures distribuitur vires quae in ipsa intelligentiae subiguntur, ac produci videtur in rectum dum a divinitate labitur in naturam. In quo quidem descensu ab intelligentia summa in tres profluit vires inferiores, id est, in discursum quendam rationalem, in sensum, in vegetandi virtutem, quemadmodum et triangulus a signo productus in tres deducitur angulos. Dico autem animam ex omnium genere primam

et ex pluribus quodammodo viribus commisceri et in rectum, ut ita dixerim, cadere. Mens enim angelica super [Plat. Op. semper] animam inferioribus intra se nullis indiget viribus, sed pura [Op. plura] mens est totaque mens atque sufficiens. Item ad inferiora non vergit sed in divinitatem solam, unde est, circuli more convertitur. Ideoque eius actio circulo comparatur. Una enim actio est et aequalis, sicut ex una et aequali linea circulus et mira quaedam utriusque capacitas. Praeterea circulus prima [Op. om. ] est et ultima figurarum: prima quidem quia una circum contentus est linea; ultima quia figurae ex pluribus lineis constitutae, quo [Op. qua] plures subeunt facies eo propinquius [Op. proquinquius] paulatim ad circuli formam quasi finem videntur accedere. Similiter et intellectus omnium primus procreatur a Deo; et intellectualis vultus, id est, absolutus ordo rerum ultimus omnium in speculo naturae refulget. Ad quem [Op. om. ] naturales formae quasi finem magis gradatim magisque accedunt."

Chapter 28 is entitled "De compositione animae et quod per quinarium in ea componenda opportune proceditur."


96

Given this fully worked-out analogy of the soul with the triangle, preeminently the right-angled triangle, and given that the triangle is the premier figure of the planar realm, Ficino clearly thinks of soul, or at least of soul in its fallen triplicity as planar.[44] Indeed, given the variety of geometrical and arithmetical structures that govern our notion of a two-dimensional realm, the plane and its subdivisions are ideally suited to modeling the complex and ambivalent status of soul and its various faculties as intermediary between the three-dimensional body and the paradoxically linear or circular realm of pure mind—linear because it is both one and many, and circular because it is "one and equal" like the line that returns upon itself to constitute the figure that is not a figure but rather the principle and end of figures. Furthermore, the secret of the planar realm of the triangle for Ficino is the notion of power, of squaring and square-rooting;[45] for it is this alone which enables us to comprehend the complex, invisible proportionality and comparability of hypotenuse to side.

If the habitus is, or functions like, a planar, and specifically a square, number or the root of such a number, it would serve in unexpected ways to validate the efficacy of, and to enlarge the scope of, a purely

[44] In his Timaeus Commentary 34 (Opera , p. 1460), having discussed the lambda numbers, Ficino goes on to describe a metaphysical triangle governed by the double, sesquialteral, and sesquitertial properties: its apex is essence and its two sides consist of the infinite, difference, and motion, and of the limit, identity, and rest (the fundamental ontological categories explored in the Sophist and Philebus , see my Icastes , chapter 2). He concludes with postulating a corresponding triangle for the soul: its unity is its essence, its will the infinite, its understanding the limit, its imagination difference, its reason identity, its power to procreate (generandi vis ) motion, its power to join (connectendi virtus ) rest. The whole topic awaits investigation.

[45] In Greek the term dunamis can refer either to the square of a number or to its square root; compare, for instance, Plato's Republic 9.587D9 (square) with the Theaetetus 147D3 ff. (square root). See Thomas L. Heath, A History of Greek Mathematics , 2 vols. (Oxford, 1921), 1:155.


97

mathematical magic and with it privilege the beings preeminently gifted in Ficino's view for the subtleties of mathematics, namely the daemons. We might imagine a special mathematical dimension for the lower daemons on the one hand in supervising the diet, regimen, and exercise that ensure an even habitus in the body; and for the higher daemons on the other in disciplining the soul—over and beyond, that is, instructing it in ordinary mathematical procedures—so that it too attains an even habitus . But nowhere would their role be more arresting than in the case of the habitus of the spiritus , since the spiritus is for Ficino the object of manipulation by magicians using the resources of natural and of astral magic (and using perhaps, however unconsciously, the mathematical structures and powers that underlie such magics). The habitus of the spirit, the hypotenuse if you will of the spirit, would be subject a fortiori to expressly mathematical manipulation, and especially to the manipulation of human and daemonic geometers, those skilled above all others in the understanding of planes and surfaces. It would lend a novel and dramatic dimension to the monitory exhortation in the vestibule to the Platonic Academy, "Let no one enter here who is not an adept in geometry,"[46] and to Plutarch's declaration, in a phrase he attributes to Plato, that "God is always working as a geometer" ("Aei theos geômetrei ").[47]

Ficino had an abiding fascination for the branch of applied geometry with a singular role in daemonic magic, namely the science of optics.[48] I have argued elsewhere that Ficino seems to have thought of the magician using his own spiritus as a mirror to catch, focus, and reflect the streams or rays of idola or images that flow ceaselessly out from animate and inanimate objects.[49] For the idola , and the spiritus that focuses the idola , are the means whereby he can work with and work upon anything, living as well as inert, from a distance. Aspects of

[46] Ficino gives a Latin rendering of this inscription in his Vita Platonis (sub Discipuli Platonis praecipui ) (Opera , p. 766.1; trans. in Letters 3:38) and glosses it thus: "Understand that Plato was intending this to apply not only to the proper measurement of lines but also of [our] passions (affectuum )." See Chapter 1, n. 1 above.

[47] Quaestiones Convivales 8.2 (Moralia 718B–720C, specifically 718BC); the treatise is entitled: "Pôs Platôn elege ton theon aei geômetrein ." We might note that in his De Defectu Oraculorum 12 (Moralia 416C), Plutarch says that Xenocrates assimilated the equilateral triangle (where all parts are equal) to the divine class, the scalene (where all parts are unequal) to the mortal, and the isosceles (where they are mixed) to the daemonic. See Richard Heinze, Xenokrates (Leipzig, 1892), pp. 166–167, fr. 24; and Fowler, Mathematics of Plato's Academy , p. 299.

[48] See now Stephan Otto, "Geometric und Optik in der Philosophie des Marsilio Ficino," Philosophisches Jahrbuch 98 (1991), 290–313.

[49] Icastes , chapter 5.


98

his skill may be irrational or sophistical, and controlled in large part by his phantasy; but a particular magician, one skilled in mathematics, Ficino imagines as being able to draw upon numbers, I believe, and notably upon figured numbers, to effect a rational magic by way of his spiritus upon the idola . Such a magician might even consciously program his spiritus like a radar dish, tilting and rotating its planes according to geometrical formulas epitomizing and controlling particular magical operations, those formulas in other words best suited to affecting the dimensions, the angles, the powers that govern a physical world constituted from triangles and from the five regular solids to which they give rise. After all, such a geometer-magus would be exercising his sovereignty over the powers governing the optical triangles formed by the objects and the idola he wished to perceive or manipulate, the reflecting surface of his spiritus , and the line of his intelligence. Obviously such triangles would themselves consist of laterals and diagonals and have irrational and irrational powers; and double the sum of the degrees of their varying angles would invariably equal the degrees of the perfect circle of the understanding.

In exercising these geometrical powers, the geometer-magus would be drawing upon the computative and manipulative skills that Ficino and the later Platonic tradition he inherited had already assigned to the daemons. For daemons are not only the masters of mathematics, they also preside over the world of light and its optical effects and illusions, and preside too over the singular role that mirrors and prisms, reflections and refractions, play in our understanding of, and in our manipulation of, light. Moreover, they are the denizens preeminently of the world of surfaces, planes, and powers, and only the basest of them choose regularly to inhabit the three-dimensional cubicity of the physical world. In this they resemble other higher souls; for all souls are properly inhabitants, in Ficino's Platonic imagination, of the realm of planes and surfaces, though they may be imprisoned for a time in solids. In that they aspire to attain the intellectual realm, however, to become pure intellects and to contemplate the mathematicals and the Ideas of numbers, they aspire, mathematically speaking, to reach the "one and equal" line, the circling line of Nous, and ultimately to return to the unity at the apex of intelligible reality, to the One in its transcendence. Specifically, given the unique role of the triangle in Platonic mathematics and psychology (and of the Pythagorean theorem in computing the relationship of the power of the hypotenuse to the powers of the sides), we must think of the highest rational souls, those of the daemons, or at least of the higher ones who dwell far


99

above the terraqueous orb, as the lords of triangularity and of the "comparability" that governs it, triangularity being the essence of the planar realm. We might even speculate over the devious ways the daemons practice on our mathematical sanity with irrational hypotenuses and surds!

The planar world occurs of course in Nature herself in the mirrors of lakes and pools and of other water and ice surfaces, though one can think of snow, salt, sand, and even various rock surfaces, as well as of certain mist and cloud phenomena, that have planar qualities and whose surfaces reflect or refract light. Preeminently, however, it occurs in the natural faceting of crystals and precious stones. It is in the play of light on such planar surfaces that the presence of daemonic geometry and its science of powers can best be glimpsed by the geometermagus. On occasions he is able even to use his own spiritus as a mirror-plane to capture and affect the idola , immaterial and material alike, that stream off objects, and to refigure them by way of recourse to the laws of figured numbers. For physical light is the intermediary between the sensible and the purely intelligible realms, and in this regard it is spiritual in the sense that it resembles, and therefore, given the ancient formula that like affects like,[50] can be influenced by, the spiritus , the substance that mediates between the body and the soul and serves as the link, as light itself does, between the otherwise divided realms of the pure forms and of informed matter.

It was this eccentric nexus of concerns which, I believe, slowly emerged in Ficino's mind and led him to posit a problematic set of interdependent connections between magic, geometry, figural arithmetic, the daemons, and light in its various manifestations. Underlying the nexus is the notion of a mathematical power and the mysterious hold it exercises over our understanding of both planes and solids. For with this understanding, predictably, comes actual power to affect and change. In all this we can glimpse the profound impact on him of Plato's Pythagorean mathematics, and specifically of the Pythagorean theorem, and with it of Theon's discussion of diagonal powers on the one hand, and of Plato's fanciful but influential presentation in the Timaeus of a triangle-based physics on the other.

The relationship in Ficino's mind between optics, and notably daemonic optics, and music—that is, between light-wave theory and sound-wave theory and the "harmonic" proportions that govern them—has yet to be fully explored. What we must now realize, how-

[50] Cf. Plato's Gorgias 510B, Lysis 214B, Republic 1.329A, 4.425C, etc.


100

ever, is that for him the plane numbers and especially the square numbers occupy a mysterious but all-powerful position between the prime numbers and the cubes; and the mathematical functions of squaring and of square-rooting are envisaged as the powers that above all govern these plane numbers and therefore govern two-dimensional space. This is the space that constitutes preeminently the realm of the daemons, or at least of the airy daemons and the daemons inferior to them, whose spiritual "bodies" or airy "envelopes" we might think of as themselves functioning like two-dimensional surfaces, governed by their habitus , by squares and by square roots. Hence the manipulative power the daemons exercise over all two-dimensional surfaces, including each other's, and hence their innate attraction to such surfaces and especially to crystals, to faceted stones and gems, and to mirrors. But this entire planar world is, from a Platonic viewpoint, presided over by the Pythagorean geometry of hypotenuses and thus of triangles, themselves vestiges of the greatest triangle of all, the Trinity. From the geometry of the triangle we ascend to the more mysterious geometry still of the circle and thence of the point, of the unextended monad that is the image of the One.

Underlying the related concepts of the ingenium , and of the habitus of souls, spirits, and bodies, and underlying particularly their role in eugenics, Platonically conceived, is the central notion as we have seen of proportion. For the best offspring are generated, not by the mating of equals—for how can the male and the female be biologically equal?—but by the mating of unequals that are proportionate to each other. This profound commitment to proportionality underlies, of course, Ficino's and his contemporaries' hierarchy of values for marriage, for social and economic justice (which were deeply indebted to Plato's and to Aristotle's notions of distributive justice). It also underlies their artistic, educational, medical, and psychological ideas, centered as they were around the cognate idea of temperance. Indeed, it has profound and far-reaching ethical, epistemological, and ontological implications at almost every turn. Proportionality, moreover, governed the medieval and Renaissance science of harmonics, the key to the twin disciplines of music and astronomy. Hence the logic of the order in which such handbooks as Theon's and Nicomachus's treat of figural mathematics (that is, of arithmetic and geometry), stereometry, astronomy, and music.[51]

[51] Ficino again justifies this order in a 1477 letter to Giovanni Francesco Ippoliti now in the fourth book of his Epistulae (Opera , pp. 761.3–763.1; trans. in Letters

(footnote continued on the next page)


101

The subject is complex but we should look briefly at some of the psychological extensions Ficino himself raises. Chapter 12 sets out the basic model: proportion should dictate the relationships between our soul's three powers—those Ficino had invoked in chapter 28 of his Timaeus Commentary, as we have seen: the rational power (divided as it is between the exercise of the speculative intellect and that of the discursive reason), the irascible power (best conceived of as spiritedness, as vigorous striving), and the concupiscible or appetitive power.[52] During the golden, the saturnian age, the relationship of the intellect to the reason was in the ratio of 4:3, that of the reason to the irascible power in the ratio of 3:2, and that of the irascible power to the concupiscible power in the ratio of 2:1.[53] These are the three primary ratios, and they are contained musically within the diapason. During the silver, the jovian age, moreover, the same proportions pertained except that the ratio of the intellect to the reason was reversed. If we ever hope to recapture the conditions of either of these two Hesiodic ages, we must use our disciplina to ensure that these proportions are observed. But before disciplina can be effective, the same proportions, he argues, must be established, presumably by diet and by regimen, in the medical spiritus , which is composed of blood, meaning here the sanguineous vapor compounded from the vapors of all four elements.[54] In it air must exceed fire by 4:3, fire exceed water by 3:2, and water exceed earth by 2:1, the spirit being above all an airy substance related to the supremely airy beings, the daemons. In

(footnote continued from the previous page)

[3] 28–31 [no. 18]) on the grounds that numbers come before figures (meaning planes), figures before solids, solids at rest before solids in motion, and motion before "the order and reasons of voices" (meaning the musical ratios) that proceed from the motion of the heavenly spheres. Ficino derived the order from Plato's Republic 7.525B–531C, which goes on to sing "the hymn to dialectic" as the crown of the five disciplines.

[52] Following Timaeus 69C ff. and 89E ff. Other key texts on the tripartite soul are the Republic 4.436AB, 4.439D–442D, and 9.588C–589C, and the Phaedrus 246A ff. and 253C–254E. Cf. Ficino's letter of 1 July 1477 to Giovanni Nesi now in his fourth book of Epistulae (Opera , pp. 774.2–776.1; trans. in Letters 3:59–62).

[53] In his Conclusiones secundum Mathematicam Pythagorae (see n. 39 above), nos. 8, 9, and 10, Pico had declared to the contrary that the musical proportions governing the relationship of the reason to the concupiscible power, of the irascible power to the concupiscible, and of the reason to the irascible power were respectively the diapason, diapente, and diatesseron (i.e., the ratios 2:1, 3:2, and 4:3).

[54] In the De Amore 7.4 (ed. Marcel, p. 247) Ficino had defined spiritus as "a vapor of the blood." For the various senses of spiritus in Ficino see my Platonism , pp. 102–103n. In his provocative study, Eros et magie à la Renaissance, 1484 (Paris, 1984), translated into English by Margaret Cook as Eros and Magic in the Renaissance (Chicago, 1987), Ioan Petru Couliano does not observe Ficino's distinctions with sufficient care. This is a pity since spiritus , spiritual magic, and Ficino form the nub of his concerns.


102

terms of the four qualities of hot, cold, wet, and dry, the spirit is preeminently hot and dry like the heart from which its vapors arise, and unlike the two other major organs, the liver, which is hot and wet, and the brain, which is wet and cold. However, Ficino accepts the traditional prescription that in general heat should exceed coldness in us by 2:1, wetness exceed dryness by 3:2, and heat exceed wetness by 4:3. We need a daily cooking that would not be possible without these governing ratios, since heat is more important for life than wetness and is as it were that which "forms" wetness. Hence the propitiousness of such climates, places, seasons, airs, and times as observe the like proportions.[55] If they cease to obtain in us or in the surrounding air, then we die. The consequences of unbalanced proportions for nature, however—those that are themselves the result of the disruption of such primary proportions among the planets as preside over nature—are cataclysmic inundations and conflagrations.

As long as men individually and as a group are governed by these proportions, then a good habitus can be said to govern their bodies, spirits, and souls, and to govern the republic in which they dwell. Such a habitus can be maintained by disciplina . But at some point, either prematurely if disciplina is lacking, or at the duly appointed time, men begin to age and the body politic likewise. Such a duly appointed time for the state occurs at the coming of the fatal number of 1728 units—and presumably Ficino has years rather than months or days or still lesser units in mind. Individuals, whatever their own proportions and appointed times, are necessarily subject to this greater cycle of change. And 1728 is so significant precisely because, as the cube of 12, it contains the three primary ratios, 12 being, as Ficino observes, the number "in which the proportions and harmonies are first unfolded." Even at the squaring of 12—that is, even after 144 years have elapsed—"a great mutation occurs among men," though we can exploit such a mutation if we exercise our disciplina . But whatever we do by way of disciplina , we cannot prevent the greatest of all fatal mutations occurring at the 1728th year, the "highest end" of a state's destined life, and therefore of the lives of those citizens lucky or unlucky enough to be born into the state at that culminating time. For

[55] Interestingly the site of Plato's Academy was notoriously insalubrious! and Ficino's scholarly haunts were by his own admission a deal more attractive (see n. 12 above). In his epitome for the Critias (Opera , p. 1487), he examines the various conflicting views in antiquity as to whether the air of Attica was or was not tempered, views he derived, incidentally, from Proclus's In Timaeum 2 (ed. Diehl, 1:162.11–30), glossing the Timaeus 24C.


103

thereafter the fatal "law"—and this is fraught with Platonic connotations from the myth of Er at the end of the Republic —requires a falling away, though such falling away can occur long before if the magistrates have allowed the state's disciplina to relax and therefore imprudentia to take over. Ficino adds, inconsistently perhaps, that sometimes an infelicitas —presumably some kind of inscrutable misfortune—can also thwart the best of disciplines before the onset of the fatal decline.

At this point in his twelfth chapter Ficino cites the contentious passage from Aristotle's Politics 5, where Aristotle nevertheless seems to be agreeing with Plato that the onset of the fatal mutation is marked by the number that is among those whose proportions are "contained in the ratio of 4:3 joined to the 5." As we have seen, Ficino interprets Aristotle to mean that Plato is signifying first the 12, the number that contains, like the diapason, the three ratios of 4:3, 3:2, and 2:1; and then the process by which 12 becomes a plane as the equilateral 144, and next, "at the third augmentation," a solid as 1728. Furthermore, Aristotle also introduces the contrasting notions of "nature" and of "discipline."

Behind this analysis of the principles of auspicious breeding and sturdy citizen disciplina lies a haunting sense of inauspicious time and of fatal necessity, and a classical-medieval awareness, found memorably too in the Book of Ecclesiastes, of the inexorable cycling of history. Both are seemingly at odds with Ficino's humanist commitments to the theme of the dignity of man and his will and the autonomy of his choices and deliberations. We are many degrees distant certainly from the naive anthropocentrism sometimes attributed to Ficino (and to Pico) by historians in the Burckhardtian tradition, often in laudatory or admiring tones.[56] But this duality of mood and expectation was implicit in Plato's own dual prescriptions in the Republic . On the one hand, and with the zeal of a dedicated social engineer, he had detailed in book 5 the correct times and conditions to mate couples; and on the other, and with the disengagement of a quietist or contemplative, he had spoken in book 8 of the ineluctable sway exercised over such mundane concerns by the greater numbers of time. In effect, two very

[56] Guilty in this regard are the stimulating chapters recently devoted to Ficino and Pico by William Kerrigan and Gordon Braden in The Idea of the Renaissance (Baltimore and London, 1989), pp. 101–133, where to Ficino is attributed an "unrepressed, unembarrassed, trouble-free" account of "self-deification" (p. 114), and where "Piconian man" appears as "Pac-Man, existing only in the act of devouring the essential excellences of others" (p. 120)!


104

different scales of time were being addressed. The deliberated mixing by the philosopher-magistrates of castes, classes, types, and temperaments in order to produce the tempered, equable citizen in a tempered citizen body was an on-going problem dominated not only by the notion of the spousal and breeding numbers and their computation for each individual couple, but also by general considerations of seasonal propitiousness and fecundity and of astral influences. The magistrates of book 5 would have required constant access to an almanac of optimum mating times based on predictions concerning the climate, the season, and the positions of the stars; indeed, reference to such an almanac would have been part of their responsibilities, part of their exercise of the city's disciplina . But they could never have been expected to predict, at least on rational computational grounds, the onset ofthe fatal turn. The cycle is too immense for any ordinary mortal to be able to obtain a perspective on it: to plot the moment of its inception or termination and thus the period of its duration and his own location in that period. Such a determination, as we shall see, can onlybe made, if made at all, by a divinely inspired prophet or prophetastrologer.

Nonetheless, Ficino's optimism tries to assert itself: even the fatal time, once it is upon us, can provide us with an opportunity, not an occasion—to use his own antithetical terms; can provide us, that is, with the possibility of changing some things qualitatively for the better, and not merely, as in Aristotle, with an explanation as to why an ideal republic begins to disintegrate. This is because 1728 is a number that embraces various kinds of numbers, benign and malign, those signifying favorable as well as those signifying unfavorable conditions. Moreover, Ficino again adduces the mathematical schema that presents us with the cube returning to the plane, thence to the line, and thence to the point, implicitly rejecting in the process the alternative notion of a collapse into the mathematics of unequilaterals or worse. He is thereby suggesting that Plato intends both an emanation and a return of numbers and of the years they signify to the One, a systole and a diastole of time, and not an end of time for the republic, a fatal and inexorable mutation into something inferior, though this is what Plato probably had in mind.

The troubling element in this analysis remains the stars and prediction based upon the stars. For it is the knowledge of the figures, the "crossings" and "the relative reversals and progressions," of their "choric dances" as the Timaeus 40C calls them, which lies at the heart


105

of our sense of cyclicality and therefore of rebirth and renewal,[57] dances that will determine the advent of the fatal number and signify therefore whether our disciplina can yet prevail. To this astrological dimension of the De Numero Fatali we must now turn.

[57] See Garin, Lo zodiaco , chapter 1.


106

4
Jupiter, the Stars, and the Golden Age

"Iam nova progenies caelo demittitur alto"


Ironically, Ficino himself uses the ominous notion of an occasio to take up some of the astrological and astronomical implications he perceives in Plato's presentation of the geometric number, and in particular, he says, to dispute with the astrologers. In a letter to Angelo Poliziano, he had likened them to the earth giants, Antaeus and Cacus, whom Hercules had vanquished and whom Pico and Poliziano, Hercules' successors, had vanquished again in his own time.[1] Ficino's ambivalent relationship to astrology has long been the subject, however, of debate and disagreement.[2] One finds him, for instance, in the third book of his Epistulae , in the course of letters written within a few weeks, perhaps even a few days, of each other in 1476, complaining to his great friend Giovanni Cavalcanti that he

[1] The letter is dated 20 August 1494 and is now in the twelfth and last book of Ficino's Epistulae (Opera , p. 958.1).

[2] Most recently, see Garin, Lo zodiaco della vita , chapter 4; Giancarlo Zanier, La medicina astrologica e la sua teoria: Marsilio Ficino e i suoi critici contemporanei (Rome, 1977), pp. 5–60; D. P. Walker, "Ficino and Astrology," in Garfagnini, Ritorno 2:341–349; Carol V. Kaske, "Ficino's Shifting Attitude towards Astrology in the De Vita Coelitus Comparanda , the Letter to Poliziano, and the Apologia to the Cardinals," in Garfagnini, Ritorno 2:371–381; eadem, "Introduction," in Marsilio Ficino: Three Books on Life , ed. and trans. Kaske and Clark, pp. 17–70; Cesare Vasoli, "Le débat sur l'astrologie ô Florence: Ficin, Pic de la Mirandole, Savonarole," in Divination et controverse en France au XVIe siècle (Paris, 1987), pp. 19–33; Brian P. Copenhaver, "As-

trology and Magic," in The Cambridge History of Renaissance Philosophy , ed. Charles B. Schmitt et al. (Cambridge, 1988), pp. 274–285; and Melissa Meriam Bullard, "The Inward Zodiac: A Development in Ficino's Thoughts on Astrology," Renaissance Quarterly 43.4 (1990), 687–708. References to earlier scholarship can be found in Kaske's authoritative "Introduction." For Ficino's place in the larger context, Garin's work has been especially illuminating.

Bullard's recent thesis that Ficino gradually internalizes astrology neglects evidence both from the later years when Ficino is often very much concerned with traditional astrology, and from the early years when he frequently internalizes it: outward and inward zodiacs, that is, coexisted in his thinking throughout his life. This is made especially clear by his famous letter to Lorenzo di Pierfrancesco de' Medici, now in the fifth book of his Epistulae (Opera , pp. 805.2–806; trans. in Letters 4:61–63 [no. 46]), which argues that the heavens are also within, "Non enim sunt haec alicubi nobis extra quaerenda, nempe totum in nobis est coelum" (and cf. the letter immediately following to Giorgio Antonio Vespucci, Opera , p. 806.2). A similar objection undermines Walker's attempt to redate the Disputatio and thus arrive at one anti-astrological phase, inspired by Savonarola, late in Ficino's career. The De Numero Fatali has material that both scholars were unfamiliar with; and the Timaeus Commentary and the De Vita , two major texts, also sit on the proverbial fence with both ears to the ground! Ficino was always open, moreover, to figurative banter; see, for instance, the letter to the Cardinal of Siena in the first book of his Epistulae (ed. Gentile, pp. 234–235; trans. in Letters 1:195–196 [no. 128]).

For a Jungian perspective on Ficino as the practitioner, even the inventor, of a psychological or "esoteric" astrology, see Angela Voss, "Ficino and Astrology," The Astrologers' Quarterly 60 (1986), 126–138, 191–199 (with references on p. 136 n. 2 to the similar views of James Hillman, Thomas Moore, and Liz Greene).


107

could not be writing to him, according to the astronomers, at a more inauspicious hour; to the Archbishop of Florence, Rinaldo Orsini, that he had been prevented from rendering thanks to him personally by "a malign aspect of Saturn which was square to the Moon"; to the Bishop of Volterra, Antonio degli Agli, that, while some had attributed the current "calamity in the church" to the retrogression of Saturn in Leo and of Jupiter in Pisces, his own view was rather that "stars are adverse only to those with perverse minds"; and to Cavalcanti again that his melancholy was indeed due to that retrogression of Saturn in Leo, more particularly since Saturn had set the seal of melancholy upon him from his birth, even if he was perhaps indebted to the planet, as Cavalcanti had argued, for his scholarly powers, or rather to God who is the beginning and end of all.[3]

Such vacillation is typical in the letters and is frequently tuned to the amicable or complimentary occasion. But one finds it throughout his works, the two extremes being the incredulous but incomplete

[3] Opera , pp. 724.2, 726.3, 729.3, 731.3–733.1; trans. in Letters 2:11, 15–16, 24–25, 30–34 (nos. 4, 10, 17, 22, 23 [a letter by Cavalcanti], 24). See Klibansky, Panofsky, and Saxl, Saturn and Melancholy , pp. 257–258.

The third book comprises letters dating from August 1476 to May 1477.


108

Disputatio contra Iudicium Astrologorum of 1477,[4] and the credulous but complete De Vita of 1489, whose three books set forth in encyclopedic detail the kind of help that the astrological lore of planetary and stellar influences and the natural and medical lore of sympathies and antipathies together can provide us with in our quest for a longer and better life, particularly as scholars; and whose theories led to Ficino's being accused briefly before Pope Innocent VIII of heresy and magic, despite his garland of caveats, qualifications, and invocations of Aquinas in the offending third book.[5] Here I shall focus upon the points that he raises in the De Numero Fatali and that are germane to our understanding of his interpretation of the mathematical "mystery" in book 8 of Plato's Republic . For they provide us with evidence that has not hitherto been weighed or even recognized concerning his views on astrology, and on the nature of human choice and human freedom that astrology calls continually into question. They also affect our ability to arrive at a full appreciation of the subtle discriminations, and nor merely indecisions or confusions, that Ficino customarily drew upon in formulating his reactions both towards the universally accepted notion that the stars influence the sublunar world of nature and of man, and towards the theological problem of future contingents that that notion necessarily raises.

In a moral essay entitled "How False Is Human Prosperity," again in the third book of his Epistulae , Ficino addresses Bernardo Bembo, the Venetian ambassador, and outlines what he calls the four universal "causes" of the transiency of earthly happiness as designated by the philosophers: divine providence; "the fateful law of heavenly bodies," which is tempered by divine providence; the "natural order," which arranges the elements under the heavens and their fateful law; and the "human" cause in its degenerate form as "free licence" (solutior licencia ), arrogance, and insolence.[6] It is clear from this, and from similar passages, that Ficino views all events involving man as the result of these four causes working, now in harmony, now in discord, under

[4] Ed. Kristeller, Supplementum 2:11–76. See Gentile in Mostra , pp. 97–99 (no. 74), and Vasoli, "Le débat sur l'astrologie," pp. 22–26.

[5] See Paul Oskar Kristeller, "Marsilio Ficino and the Roman Curia," Humanistica Lovaniensia 34A (1985), 83–99 at 93–95; also Kaske, "Introduction," pp. 55–70, and, more generally, Brian P. Copenhaver, "Scholastic Philosophy and Renaissance Magic in the De Vita of Marsilio Ficino," Renaissance Quarterly 37 (1984), 523–554. Ficino's accusers are unknown and no documents on the matter have come to light; it was quietly resolved in his favor.

[6] Opera , pp. 722.2–723; trans. in Letters 2:5–8 (no. 2).


109

the rule or the divine law of providence. Fate as the "law" governing the celestial realm is the minister of this providence and the governor in turn of nature and its order; it is associated preeminently with Jupiter as the presiding deity of law. Insofar as the different faculties of man participate in different realms, they are governed by providence, fate, nature, and their own desire and passions. That is to say, man's intuitive intelligence (mens ) and his free will (arbitrium ) are governed by providence,[7] while his discursive reason is governed by fate, the faculties of his lower soul by nature, and his body by his passions.[8] What then is the kind and the degree of their interaction? What is the timing and the agency of the ideal accord that will banish all discord and make these warring faculties part of a unified whole in man, and man part of a unitary moment in tumultuous nature, and nature at one with the moving heavens and their law, and all subservient to eternal providence, which, as the opening letter of book 4 addressed to Lorenzo Franceschi declares, will "gently temper stern fate in accordance with the good"?[9] To answer this question, which lies at the core of

[7] Cf. Ficino's letter to Cavalcanti in the first book of his Epistulae (ed. Gentile, pp. 97–98; trans. in Letters , 1:94–95 [no. 50]): "the force of fate does not penetrate the mind unless the mind of its own accord has first become submerged in the body which is subject to fate"; also the letter of 28 June 1477 to Francesco Marescalchi, now in the fourth book (Opera , p. 776.3; trans. in Letters 3:63–64 [no. 29]), which insists on the fact that the mind (mens ) and the "free judgement of the will" (liberum voluntatis arbitrium ) are above the compulsion of "celestial fate" and are guided rather by "supercelestial providence" ("quasi non a coelesti fato coactus fuerit sed a supercoelesti tum Dei providentia tum mentis libertate perductus"). Instances could be multiplied. See Charles Trinkaus, In Our Image and Likeness: Humanity and Divinity in Italian Humanist Thought , 2 vols. (London, 1970), 2:476–478.

[8] Cf. Ficino's Platonic Theology 13.2 (ed. Marcel, 2:206–214). Despite the authority of this work, this is not his clearest account of the relationship between providence, fate, and nature, and the human faculties of the mens, ratio, idolum, and natura . Not only does he encounter problems in integrating the ancient concept of the idolum , but he is intent on schematically isolating our ratio : whereas our mens is tied (subnectatur ) to providence, our idolum to fate, and our single natura to universal nature, our ratio is free to ally itself now with this faculty, now with that ("per rationem nostri iuris sumus omnino") (p. 211). But our true goal is to become one with our mens and thus one with providence. As Kaske notes in her "Introduction," p. 59, Ficino's vacillations always left intact "his orthodox and sincere belief in free will"; for which in particular see the Platonic Theology 9.4. In general, see Kristeller, Philosophy of Ficino , pp. 368–388.

[9] Opera , p. 751.3–752; trans. in Letters 3:3–4 (no. 1). The letter is undated, but book 4 includes letters in the main from 1 March to 1 August 1477. Even the De Vita rejects the notion of an inimical heaven: at 2.16.1–3 (ed. Kaske and Clark) Ficino declares that there is no hate among the stars, only movement and diversity. Hence malefic Mars and Saturn are ultimately beneficial in the sense that their influences play a part in the celestial harmony; see Kaske, "Introduction," p. 34. This would imply that fate is always beneficent, something that, however philosophically persuasive the arguments, flies in the face of ordinary experience.


110

Greek philosophy, Ficino again resorts, like Plato in the Timaeus before him, to geometrical proportion and the three primary ratios.[10]

In speaking of the proportions that must ideally pertain in the balance of man's bodily humors and in the climate and air of a salubrious place, Ficino assumes in chapter 12 that these govern the four primary qualities of hotness, coldness, wetness, and dryness in us and our habitus , and also and preeminently the influences of the "life-giving" planets on our lives.[11] If we are ever to seize the proper opportunity—"to capture the favor of the heavens as best we can" (a notion with a long and intricate history and one of the leitmotifs of Ficino's De Vita )[12] —then we must start with the fundamental recognition that, since the "distance" of Jupiter to Venus is in the ratio of 4:3, that of Venus to the Sun of 3:2, and that of the Sun to the Moon of 2:1, we should be influenced by these four in the same ratios. For the Sun and the Moon bestow life in itself, while Jupiter and Venus bestow prosperity, increase, and fertility besides, though in these dual pairings the Sun and Jupiter are the senior partners.[13] In "elections" therefore we must begin by assigning the proportional values of 4, 3, 2, and 1 to Jupiter, Venus, the Sun, and the Moon respectively.[14] This has nothing of course to do with the actual distances of the planets from the Earth in the Ptolemaic scheme, nor, as we might otherwise expect, with their angular distances from each other and thus with their "aspects." It refers rather, as Ficino's reference to his own epitome for the Epinomis clearly demonstrates, to the musical intervals between the planetary spheres. Thus, if the interval of the Earth to the Moon is a fourth, of

[10] See Leo Spitzer, Classical and Christian Ideas of World Harmony: Prolegomena to the Interpretation of the Word "Stimmung," ed. A. G. Hatcher (Baltimore, 1963); and E. A. Lippman, Musical Thought in Ancient Greece (New York, 1964), esp. chapter 1.

[11] Cf. Ptolemy, Tetrabiblos 1.4–8. The humoral theory had the effect of bonding medicine to astronomy-astrology and both to harmonics, meaning the science of ratios and proportions. On the ideal proportions, the balance, among the humors, cf. De Vita 1.5.47–75, and Kaske, "Introduction," p. 31.

[12] It is this "elective" or "catarchic" (katarchikos ), rather than "interrogatory" or horary, astrology that Kaske maintains is Ficino's principal concern ("Introduction," pp. 36–38); see Chapter 3, n. 5 above. The third book deals with the controversial topic of capturing planetary influences by way of talismans and images.

[13] In the De Vita at 3.5.3–5 he identifies Jupiter, Venus, and the Sun as the three Graces; and at 3.6.40 ff. he virtually identifies the Sun with Jupiter. Deciding on the preeminence of any one of these good planets, particularly of the Sun or Jupiter, is an elaborate game and depends on one's point of view.

[14] See Eugenio Garin, "Le 'elezioni' e il problema dell'astrologia," in L'età nuova (Naples, 1969), pp. 421–447; it first appeared in Umanesimo e esoterismo: Atti del V Convegno Internazionale di Studi Umanistici , ed. Enrico Castelli (Padua, 1960), pp. 17–37.


111

Earth to the Sun a fifth, of the Sun to the firmament another fourth, then the interval of Jupiter to Venus is another fourth, of Venus to the Sun another fifth, and so on.[15] One wonders how far Ficino meant us to pursue the establishment of correspondences between differing relationships that share the same ratios, between the spirit, say, and the life-giving planets, both of which embrace in different ways the same ratios and suggest therefore that the four planets constitute a kind of spirit or even represent the World-Spirit that the De Vita had ingeniously postulated as linking the World-Soul to the World-Body. In

[15] Platonis Opera Omnia (1491), fol. 324v (sig. R4v) (i.e., Opera , p. 1529):

Pythagorici enim, ubi spherarum intervalla dimetiuntur, terram ad firmamentum comparant, item ad lunam et solem, solem quoque ad firmamentum. In quibus sane comparationibus intervallum a terra ad solem comparatum ad intervallum ab eodem ad firmamentum efficit quidem inter terram ac solem sesquialteram, inter hunc vero et firmamentum sesquitertiam; et in illa quidem proportione diapente consonantia nascitur, ex hac autem diatessaron; ex quibus certe ambabus conficitur proportio dupla consonantiaque diapason. Volunt et a terra ad lunam fieri diatessaron, sicut ad solem fit diapente, et a sole ad firmamentum iterum diatessaron. Quemadmodum vero natura proportiones eiusmodi observat in spheris, ita in actionibus passionibusque elementorum.

For, in measuring the intervals of the spheres, the Pythagoreans compare the Earth to the firmament, and again to the Moon and the Sun, and the Sun too to the firmament. In these comparisons the interval from the Earth to the Sun is contrasted with the interval from the Sun to the firmament. Thus there is a sesquialteral interval [of 3:2] between the Earth and the Sun, but a sesquitertial interval [of 4:3] between the Sun and the firmament. From the first proportion is born the consonance of diapente, from the second that of diatessaron. From both together comes the double proportion or consonance of the diapason. The Pythagoreans also want the interval from the Earth to the Moon to be a fourth (just as that from the Earth to the Sun is a fifth, and that from the Sun to the firmament is again a fourth). In the same way that nature observes such proportions among the spheres, so it observes them too in the actions and passions of the elements.

Cf. Theon, Expositio 3.15; Macrobius, Somnium Scipionis 2.1.1–25, 2.4.1–10; and Ficino's own De Rationibus Musicae (ed. Kristeller, Supplementum , 1:51–56). This tuning system was known to both antiquity and the Renaissance as "the eight-stringed lyre of Pythagoras."

In his Timaeus Commentary 35 (Opera , p. 1461.1), Ficino propounds another analysis of the planetary "distances," this time in terms of the lambda. His proximate source is Macrobius, Somnium Scipionis 2.3.14–15, who attributes it to Porphyry; their ultimate source is of course the Timaeus 35B ff. In the Porphyrian order the proportionate "distances" from Earth are: to the Moon 1, to the Sun 2 (being double that of Earth to Moon), to Venus 3 (being triple that of Earth to Sun), to Mercury 4 (being quadruple that of Earth to Venus), to Mars 9 (being nine times that of Earth to Mercury), to Jupiter 8 (being eight times that of Earth to Mars), and to Saturn 27 (being twenty-seven times that of Earth to Jupiter). The left foot of the lambda therefore becomes Moon-Sun-Mercury-Jupiter, the right foot Moon-Venus-Mars-Saturn. Whether these twin alignments (which privilege the Moon) are especially significant for Ficino is doubtful, but he does stress that the arrangement gives the solid numbers (meaning the

cubes) to "the graver planets Jupiter and Saturn." He goes on to note, "Although I have elsewhere reviewed other measures for the planetary intervals according to the opinion of several Pythagoreans, yet I esteem these Platonic measures the more probable. Perhaps we can use these measures to understand those in the tenth book of the Republic which are more obscure and concern the spheres. Again we can use what we have said here about the power of numbers and proportions to conjecture what might be involved in the eighth book of the Republic and what it has to say about the celestial circuit and numbers and proportions." The lambda, in other words, can help to explain the passages on the sirens and on the fatal and perfect numbers!

See Heninger, Touches of Sweet Harmony , pp. 93–100, 179–187.


112

any event, Ficino is enjoining us before all else to contemplate the harmonies of the spheres, and to attune our spirit to those harmonies.[16]

Though linked with the Sun in the musical ratio of 2:1, the Moon is in many ways an anomaly: it should be considered, he says in chapter 14, in terms of its ever-changing aspects to the six other planets (again privileging 6 as a number), while the six other planets should be considered in terms of their varying aspects not so much to each other as to the sphere of the fixed stars. And Ficino speaks loosely here of a kind of proportionality between the relationship of the Moon to the other planets, and of these to the sphere of the fixed stars (and of the "humor of the elements" to the Moon and of their heat to the Sun). As the planet presiding over humor, the Moon presides over the durations of animal and vegetative life, and is thus of particular concern to the doctor as well as the farmer, the gardener, and those dependent on the tides.[17]

Once again, however, Ficino is drawn to the particular mathematical categories he has already used to decipher Plato's enigmatic passage on the fatal number, although he is not working with a tightly organized series of analogies and is continuously aware of conceptual parallax: what is odd or unequilateral in one context can be viewed as even or equilateral in another, depending on what is being measured. Since the even numbers and the equilateral numbers (which are alternately odd and even) can signify the firmament and its stars (especially of course 100 and 10,000, their geometric mean being the unequilateral 1000), the odd numbers and the unequilateral numbers (all of which are even and are either long or oblong and which include, we recall, the perfect number 6) must signify the planets. The more regu-

[16] This great Pythagorean theme, sanctioned as it was by Plato's account of the sirens in the Republic 10.617B, Ficino treated on many occasions, beginning perhaps with his early treatise De Divino Furore . This was addressed to Peregrino Agli and dated 1 December 1457; it is now in the first book of his Epistulae (ed. Gentile, pp. 19–28 [no. 6]; trans. in Letters 1:42–48 [no. 7]).

[17] See Kaske, "Introduction," p. 36.


113

lar planets, Saturn, Jupiter, Venus, and the Sun, are long, while Mars, Mercury, and the Moon are oblong, because they are the authors of the greatest "motions" among the planets. Contrariwise, if we compare the planets to the elements, then the planets, because their motion is comparatively even, must be associated with the equilateral numbers. Similarly with the associations of odd or even numbers. If we look at the planets in relation to each other and not to the firmament, then we must assign evenness to the Sun, to Jupiter, to Venus, and among the elemental spheres to the aether and to the middle air; and we must assign oddness to the Moon, Mercury, Mars, and Saturn, and to fire, water, and earth (though this distribution among the elements is uneven and arbitrary).

Chapter 14 assumes, furthermore, that Plato is attributing both plane and solid numbers to the planets. The solid numbers are attributed to the planets which "have the fullness of their class," that is, to Sol, Jupiter, and Saturn, the Sun signifying fertility in general, Saturn the fertility of the incorporeal and divine life, and Jove the contrasting fertility of corporeal life and of human action (Ficino inherited these distinctions from the Neoplatonic interpretation of certain arresting phrases in the Cratylus and the Laws ).[18] The plane numbers by contrast are attributed to Mars and the Moon as ministers of Sol, to Mercury as the minister of Saturn (the former's swiftness tempers the latter's tardiness), and to Venus as the minister of Jove.[19] Interestingly, these comments seem to be privileging being solid over being plane, even though the planar realm is closer to the dimensionless world of pure intelligibility. Among the plane planets, additionally, some are "lateral," some "diagonal" ("diametral"). Thus the Moon is a diagonal to Venus's lateral in that, while Venus presides over

[18] Cratylus , 395E–396C (cf. 410D); Laws 4.713A–714A; also Plotinus, Enneads 3.5.9 (esp. 9.18 ff.: "but Intellect possesses itself in satiety [en korôi ]"), and Proclus, Platonic Theology 5.5, 22, 25 (ed. and trans. Saffrey and Westerink, 5:21.1–24.21, 78.26–83.26, 96.5–7). Cf. Ficino's Philebus Commentary 1.11, 26, 27 (ed. Allen, pp. 135–137, 243–247, 253), his Cratylus epitome (Opera , p. 1311), and, for Jove, his De Vita 3.6.7–8. For his Plotinian etymologizing of Saturn as deriving from satur "filled or sated," see, for example, his Phaedrus Commentary 10 (ed. Allen, p. 111); and cf. Pico's letter to Ficino in the eighth book of Ficino's Epistulae (Opera , p. 889.4). See my Platonism , chapter 5.

The notion of Saturn's fullness or satiety is of course in stark contrast with the astrological image of him as the senile, debile, and tardy Father Time (the Cronos-Chronos pun derives from antiquity).

[19] An oft-repeated arrangement: see, for instance, Ficino's letter to Bernardo Bembo in the fifth book of his Epistulae (Opera , p. 799.1; trans. in Letters 4:44–45 [no. 30]).


114

love and conception, the Moon (as Lucina) possesses the power over birth—and Ficino has in mind specifically the birth of Love from Venus's side. Similarly Mars is a diagonal to Mercury's lateral. These diagonal-lateral relationships enable Ficino to suggest an alternative but complementary model for the distribution of the four planes among the three solids. "It is not new," he argues, "for Platonists to entertain such translations," though one wonders how far to press them.[20]

All this suggests that for the Florentine, as for Proclus before him (though this he could not know), the passage in the Republic book 8 had profound astrological implications and that the geometric number was fraught with secret planetary formulas and significations. In commenting upon it, Ficino chose not to adopt the confrontational positions championed by his "brother Platonist," Pico della Mirandola, in his sustained polemic against the astrologers, the Disputationes adversus Astrologiam Divinatricem , a work that Ficino admired and praised in other contexts.[21] Rather he is setting forth, in the main though not exclusively, the assumptions of a "high" Platonic astrology concerned with the geometrical ratios that govern the heavenly bodies and their spheres (as the Timaeus and Epinomis had declared), assumptions—or at least their implications—that must be kept quite distinct from those which underlie divinatory or predictive astrology, whether genethliacal or horary.[22] Nonetheless, he is not rejecting that ordinary astrology entirely: after all, he had to account for the Republic 's explicit admonition to the magistrates to allow marriage and conception in the com-

[20] For "translation" cf. Ficino's Timaeus Commentary 35 (Opera , p. 1461.1): "Dupla igitur et tripla et caetera intervalla in prima numerorum figura descripta Plato inveniri arbitratus in sphaeris, ad animae partes et vires unde in sphaeris translata sunt retulit."

[21] Again see Ficino's letter to Angelo Poliziano of 20 August 1494 (cf. n. 1 above): "Astrologica portenta fuisse a Pico nostro Mirandula singulariter confutata. Quae enim ego nusquam affirmo, immo et cum Plotino derideo, explodi a Mirandula gaudeo, superstitiosam praeterea vanitatem ab illo tanquam a Phoebo Pithonicum virus extingui tecum Politiane congratulor."

Ficino's own treatise Disputatio contra Iudicium Astrologorum , together with its accompanying 1477 letter to Francesco Ippoliti—now in the fourth book of his Epistulae (Opera , pp. 781.2–782.1; trans. in Letters 3:75–77 [no. 37])—attacks the astrologers for three pernicious errors: denying God His providence, denying justice to the angels who move the celestial spheres, and denying free will to man. Ficino rejects the fallacious argument that fate can compel men to deny fate, and he pours scorn on the inability of the astrologers to make a success, financial and otherwise, of their own lives.

[22] For the distinctions, see Chapter 3, n. 5 above. We should recall that Ficino had no hesitation in giving the pope astrological advice when the curial dust-cloud raised by his De Vita had barely settled. See Walker, Spiritual and Demonic Magic , p. 53.


115

monwealth only at the most auspicious times. In order to determine the imminence of such "opportunities," the magistrates would have had to consult presumably either their own or the nocturnal council's interpretation of the positions of the planets at a precise moment, "dancing the fairest and most magnificent of all the dances in the world," as the Epinomis suggests at 982E; or else they would have had to turn to the advice of professional astrologers.

Indeed, professional astrologers had been kept frenetically busy accounting for the portentous events of the 1480s and 1490s, and notably for the decade between 1484—the date of the publication, as we have seen, of Ficino's great Plato translation—and 1494, the year that witnessed the deaths of Poliziano and Pico, the expulsion of Piero de' Medici, the advent of Charles VIII, and the triumph of Savonarola. These events and the blaze of astrological activity attending them would explain in themselves the intensity of Ficino's engagement with a question raised by Plotinus, who had been the primary focus of his scholarly activity for the first eight years of that decade: namely, what is the degree to which the stars play a determining in addition to a signifying role, not only over nature and the corporeal realms, but over the lives of men and over the "lives" of their social and even their intellectual institutions?[23] If wary of giving much credence to astrological prediction, particularly in the light of Pico's corrosive reiteration in the Disputationes of the many objections traditionally brought to bear on the accuracy of astronomical observation and computation, Ficino was still haunted, and perhaps increasingly so in these turbulent later years, by a vague sense that the stars had presided not just over his health and temperament, but over his life's work as a scholar and interpreter, and thus over the destiny of his attempt to revive the spirit of Plato. We have a number of intimations—notably in his exchange with Janus Pannonius,[24] and in his well-known letter to the as-

[23] Of particular importance here were Plotinus's treatises, the Enneads 2.3 [52 in the chronological order], "Are the stars causes?" which begins, "That the course of the stars indicates what is going to happen in particular cases, but does not itself cause everything, as most people think, has been said before elsewhere" (trans. Armstrong); and 3.1 [3 in the chronological order], the treatise on fate, the treatise to which 2.3 is almost certainly referring. See Ficino's detailed commentaries in his Opera , pp. 1609–1642, 1671.3–1684. The problem was of ancient standing; see Auguste Bouché-Leclercq, L'astrologie grecque (Paris, 1899), pp. 600–604.

[24] Opera , p. 871.2 (Janus's letter to Ficino accusing him of curiositas for his attempt to revive the theology of the ancients and querying the authority contemporary astrologers had bestowed upon that attempt) and pp. 871.3–872 (Ficino's reply invoking the role of providence)—they occur towards the beginning of the eighth book of

Ficino's Epistulae . See Hankins, Plato , pp. 302–303; and Gentile, Ficino: Lettere 1: xxxv–xxxvi. This Janus, incidentally, is not the famous bishop of Pécs (1434–1472), as Hungarian scholars since Huszti in 1924 have repeatedly pointed out; see Marianna D. Birnbaum, Janus Pannonius, Poet and Politician (Zagreb, 1981), pp. 167–168, with further references.


116

trologer-bishop Paul of Middelburg[25] —that he regarded this revival and his role in it as something that had been configured, or at least signified, by the stars circling in their "fairest dance."

Perhaps no text is more prominent in this regard than the conclusion he wrote for the preface to his translation of Plotinus's treatise, the Enneads 3.4. Speculating as to why certain men achieve extraordinary feats even though they lack teachers and other resources, he underscores the role of personal daemons: it is they who arrange for the various factors such as the occasion, the place, the necessary people and equipment, and so on, to conjoin. These daemons are subject to particular planets and their houses, however, and to particular celestial dispositions. To that degree our entering upon some ultimately successful design is always predetermined by the stars. But Ficino hastens to assert that it is up to ourselves to follow through; for the completion of that design will almost certainly occur long after the heavenly aspects that presided over its inception have passed away, never in a lifetime to return. Hence we may deduce that the stars signify but do not directly or wholly cause the successful attainment of some goal; but the goal was made possible nonetheless by a daemon subject to the stars. If the final and perfecting cause is in ourselves, yet the efficient cause remains a heavenly disposition.[26]

The taproot that sustained this equivocal approach to stellar agency was not Ficino's attempt to reconcile various passages in Plato that are open to a fatalistic reading—those, for instance, in the Republic , the Timaeus , the Laws , and the Epinomis 27 —with others that stress the soul's freedom or autonomy, though his impulse to reconcile, adjust, and syncretize was overriding. Rather, it was his medical, or perhaps

[25] Opera , p. 944.3 (dated 13 September 1492—this is the last item in the eleventh book of Ficino's Epistulae )—note that Averrois in the title should be aureis . In his Prognostica ad Viginti Annos Duratura (Antwerp, 1484) Paul had predicted, we recall, that 1484, the year in which Saturn was conjunct with Jupiter, heralded changes in Christianity itself; see Chapter 3, n. 1 above.

[26] Opera , pp. 1707–1709 (in Ficino's 1492 Plotini Enneades the preface appears on sig. u vii –viii . See my "Summoning Plotinus: Ficino, Smoke, and the Strangled Chickens."

[27] Republic 10.617C ff., Timacus 47E ff., 86B–87B (the mind can be healthy only in a healthy body), Laws 12.960CD, Epinomis 982A ff., etc.


117

we should say his psycho-therapeutic, training and orientation, and his inability to conceive, like the vast majority of his contemporaries, of an effective regimen, let alone a pharmacopoeia, that was not governed by planetary influences. We might even contend that he was never able fully to liberate himself from his medical, and therefore from his astrological, education and experience; and accordingly from his familiarity with so much of the weighty and obscure pharmacological, lapidological, botanical, zoological, bestiarial, and daemonological lore that was the underpinning of the medical astrology which he and his contemporaries had inherited from the Aristotelian and Galenic traditions by way of the mediation and augmentation of the great Arab and Persian commentators.[28] We must remember, however, that Socrates, with varying degrees of irony as a midwife's son, regarded the philosopher as a midwife, and that the Timaeus , with its burden of medical learning in the later sections, is one of the seminal texts in the Neoplatonic tradition and authorized one of Ficino's favorite tropes: that the philosopher is the doctor of the soul.[29] We have only to look at two pieces in praise of medicine, now in the first and fourth books of his Epistulae , to see the depth of his commitment to the typically

[28] For the depth and density of his learning, see Kaske and Clark's notes and indices for their edition of the De Vita . We should bear in mind that in the Italian universities medicine and Aristotelian philosophy were closely allied, the latter being a prerequisite for the former in the degree program. Thus philosophers received a training in astrological medicine and often taught it besides (in his De Vita 3.8.69–70 Ficino agrees with Galen that a doctor must have regard to astrology, and at 3.21.51–53 he notes that Iamblichus and Apollonius of Tyana had testified that "all medicine had its origin in inspired prophecy"); see Paul Oskar Kristeller, "Philosophy and Medicine in Medieval and Renaissance Italy," in Organism, Medicine, and Metaphysics: Essays in Honor of Hans Jonas , ed. Stuart F. Spicker (Dordrecht, 1978), pp. 29–40. The medical curriculum at Bologna even had Aristotle's De Caelo as a required text; see Nancy Siraisi, Taddeo Alderotti and His Pupils (Princeton, 1981), p. 152 (as cited in Kaske, "Introduction," pp. 81–82).

[29] This derives from Plato himself, or from an epitaph on Plato to the effect that Phoebus had begotten Aesculapius to heal bodies, Plato to heal souls; see Diogenes Laertius's Lives of the Philosophers 3.45 and Ficino's Vita Platonis (trans. in Letters 3:47), and cf. the dedicatory proem to Ficino's De Vita (ed. Kaske and Clark, pp. 102.21–22). Corsi in his Vita Ficini 5 (trans. in Letters 3:138) attributed to Cosimo the witticism that, while the elder Ficino had been sent to heal bodies, his son had been sent down from heaven to heal souls—Cosimo was doubtless personally hardened to the puns on cosmos and medicus long before Ficino added his quota. See Hankins, Plato , pp. 291, 326.

We should recall that Ficino had a number of medical friends and correspondents, the most notable perhaps being Pier Leoni of Spoleto, Lorenzo de' Medici's physician and a bibliophile; and that he was himself a practitioner and a theorist of medicine (notably of epidemiology) and of psychiatry.


118

Platonic tenets that "the health of the soul is in fact cared for by certain invocations to Apollo, namely by philosophical principles," and that "everything belonging to the body, good or bad, flows from the soul," and not, we might note, from the stars (though in his treatise of 1481, Consiglio contro la pestilenza, he would accuse Mars and Saturn of causing the outbreak of plague in Florence in 1478–1480!).[30]

Certainly here in the 1490s, in the last of his specifically Platonic labors, Ficino was working through a text that focuses on the biomedical problem of the inevitable exhaustion of, and the inbuilt limitations to, the life cycle of the state; and we can reasonably suppose that it must have heightened his awareness of the approaching close of his own life cycle, an awareness that surely had already been quickened by an encounter with a major illness in 1492, the year of Lorenzo's portent-shrouded demise.[31] In any event, his long professional experience as a doctor of bodies and souls and his familiarity with their cycles and rhythms—and therefore with the workings of the "harmony" of the Pythagoreans in embryology, in the development, maturation, and dissolution of all animate entities, in the life itself of diseases physical and mental—must have deepened his understanding not just of the inevitability but of the measurability, at least in certain instances of sick-

[30] Opera , pp. 645.2–646 (ed. Gentile, pp. 142–145), 759.2–760; trans. in Letters 1:127–130 (no. 81)—a letter to Tommaso Valeri—and 3:22–25 (no. 14)—a speech written in his youth presumably for an academic audience. I am citing from the speech. In Ptolemy's Tetrabiblos 1.5, Mars and Saturn are described as the lesser and greater "misfortunes"; and this is their traditionally malefic role, which Ficino of course rejected when he turned away from predictive to elective astrology.

[31] There are numerous contemporary witnesses to the events immediately preceding and accompanying Lorenzo's death on 8 April 1492, which included comets, meteors, wolves heard in the countryside, will-o'-the-wisps at Careggi, and a great storm on the night of 5 April during which a lightning bolt struck the lantern of the cathedral cupola and in the resulting damage to the marbles and vaulting a falling tile broke one of the "palle" in a Medici coat of arms (on the following morning Savonarola delivered his famous apocalyptic sermon: "Ecce gladius Domini super terram cito et velociter"). See, for instance, the diary of Luca Landucci, Diario fiorentino dal 1450 al 1516 continuato da un anonimo fino al 1542 , ed. Iodoco Del Badia (Florence, 1883), pp. 63–65; and three of Ficino's letters written in the April of 1492, one now prefacing his translation of Porphyry's Vita Plotini and addressed to Piero di Lorenzo de' Medici (Opera , p. 1538.2), and two now in the eleventh book of his Epistulae , that of 15 April to the young Cardinal Giovanni de' Medici and that of 25 April to Filippo Valori, who was then the Florentine ambassador to Rome (Opera , pp. 930.4, 931.3—see Kristeller, Supplementum 1:36, for the revealing postscript to this letter in a Munich MS). For Ficino's illness, see his letter, again to Valori, of 26 June (Opera , p. 932.3). See Marcel, Marsile Ficin , pp. 512–519; and Roberto Ridolfi, Vita di Girolamo Savonarola , 2 vols. (Rome, 1952), 1:73–75; and in general Garin, Lo zodiaco , chapters 3 and 4.


119

ness, of the body's progress towards death. In this regard the later books of the Republic , culminating as they do in the story of Er's initiation into the mysteries of translation and of interpretation beyond the grave, together constitute a monitory and a premonitory text.

But if history—biological, personal, and institutional—is governed by durations, it is because time itself, as Plato had declared in a famous image in the Timaeus 37D–38E, is the "moving image of eternity"; and because our notion of time is keyed from the beginning to our mathematical, and not just to our observational, understanding of the relative motions of the planets, preeminently of the Sun and the Moon, and of the interplay of their cycles and epicycles, their progressions and retrogressions.[32] How then does Ficino conceive of the planetary motions, the signifiers and the causes of the moving course of time and of the history of man in time?33

He begins his first chapter with some key definitions of the movements assigned to the celestial spheres or circles, stressing in particular Plato's distinction between peritropai and periphorai . For these he is indebted in the main again to Theon.[34] The first he Latins as conversiones and takes to mean the regular circling motions of the spheres, including the planetary spheres, about their own centers—in the Ptolemaic system the Earth—and visibly and specifically the circling conversion of the sphere of the fixed stars. Periphorai he Latins as ambitus or revolutiones and takes to mean the irregularly regular circuits of the planets themselves as seen against the backdrop of the fixed stars—circuits that move at times through all four points of the compass and through retrogressions as well as progressions. The ambits of the planets are governed by the conversions of the sphere of

[32] In the Republic 7.529C–531C, in a section immediately preceding the famous allegory of the Cave, Plato had argued that the astronomer depends on his sight, as the musician on his ear. For the true mathematician, however, the stars are like diagrams that enable him to meditate upon the true numbers and figures that they merely represent: "the starry heavens . . . must necessarily be deemed inferior far to the true motions with which the real swiftness and the real slowness move in their relation to each other" (529CD). Note that the relative motions of the planets are more important than the qualities associated with them or than their influences; and important only insofar as they point to "real" swiftness or slowness.

[33] In the Laws 4.721C, in the section on "the law of marriage," the Athenian Stranger argues that mankind is "coeval with time and is ever following and will ever follow the course of time": it therefore "partakes of immortality through the generation of children."

[34] Theon, Expositio 3 passim (ed. Hiller, pp. 120.1–205.6).


120

the fixed stars, of the crystalline sphere if there is one,[35] and of the primum mobile , even as things on earth are governed by and are ultimately in accord with these ambits. The planetary revolutions thus serve to "adapt or accommodate"—meaning presumably to mediate between—the higher spherical conversions and the revolutions of all things on earth. It is therefore the conversions which ultimately ensure earthly flourishing or decline, fertility or sterility, even though the immediate "measure" is the particular planet or planetary revolution presiding not so much over a specific location or moment as over the "nature" itself of every entity. For each terrene entity—though Ficino is thinking of a living entity since he is examining the notions of fertility and sterility—is governed in particular by a planet and by one or more of that planet's revolutions or measures, and belongs to a chain of other entities under the same planet.[36] He apparently accepts this in the literal sense that one revolution of Saturn, for instance, may be the appropriate measure for one plant or animal while four revolutions is the appropriate measure for another. By "measure" he means precisely the span or duration of that entity's flourishing or life, the period during which the special or singular nature of the entity enables it to thrive. For some living beings, like insects or blossoms obviously, it is not a complete planetary ambit or measure, but merely a partial one of a few days or even hours, that determines the life span, the fatal period, of their existence.

Mysteriously, some entities—and Ficino does not specify which—are governed by conversions other than those of the planets, presumably still about the Earth as the orbital center, though these conversions are unknown to us. I believe Ficino is referring here to a recurring assumption in his thought, and one familiar to him again from the Ptolemaic tradition, that invisible constellations and stars, the paranatelonta (the thirty-six decan daemons in the faces of the zodiacal signs being the most powerful), crowd the skies and add their

[35] Ficino habitually equates it with the primum mobile ; see, for instance, his De Christiana Religione 14 (Opera , p. 19). Cf. Dante, Convivio 2.6; and Pico, Heptaplus 2.2 (ed. and trans. Eugenio Garin, Giovanni Pico della Mirandola: De Hominis Dignitate, Heptaplus, De Ente et Uno, e scritti vari [Florence, 1942], pp. 230–231), and Commento 2.15 (ibid., p. 506).

[36] The De Vita at 3.1.99–104 gives us the entities of a solar chain, and at 110–116 of a jovial one; see Copenhaver, "Scholastic Philosophy and Renaissance Magic," p. 551, with further references. For a mercurial chain, see Ficino's Phaedrus Commentary, summa 49 (ed. Allen, pp. 208–209). In general, see A.-J. Festugière, La révélation d'Hermès Trismégiste , 4 vols. (Paris, 1949–1954), 1:134.


121

influences to those of the seven visible planets, the myriad of stars and the forty-eight "universal figures" of the constellations.[37] Such invisible beings are symbolized, as we have seen, by the 100 carried to its third power. The implications of such an assumption for Ficino are legion, in that he is admitting, is indeed requiring in this instance, not so much an alternative as a vastly expanded astronomy, and therefore astrology, that takes into account the invisible signs and stars and their invisible conversiones . Whereas ordinary astrology is based upon the examination of the planetary positions and those of the zodiacal signs and may be sufficient at times for determining mundane personal and biological matters, it is clearly insufficient for determining the chronology of the great world periods. For this we need another, a metaastrology. In other words, despite his Plotinian convictions, Ficino remained tied to the notion that events and people are governed by, are attuned to, the mathematical harmonies that govern the visible and the invisible starry cycles—though individual higher souls can to a degree liberate themselves from certain of the determinations that would otherwise afflict or bind them emotionally or physically.[38] The postulation of a web of unseen ambits and conversions means that we cannot ever properly determine the time propitious for anything more than a simple physical "effect" or "operation," even though such a propitious time does in fact exist; and presumably Ficino had hoped 1484 would bring with it such an opportunity and had delayed publication of his Platonis Opera Omnia in that hope.[39] Even so, we can make some tentative approaches to the notion of propitiousness.

Propitiousness, he writes, occurs when the conversions of the heavenly spheres necessary for the "effect" are in a particular harmony or accord with the stellar and planetary revolutions necessary also for the effect, seen or unseen. This particular harmony only occurs or reoc-

[37] See Ficino's own De Vita 3.1.46–55 and 3.18.2–8. Cf. Macrobius, In Somnium Scipionis 2.20, and Pico, Heptaplus 2.4–5. For the "figures" and other technical terms, see Franz Boll, Carl Bezold, and Wilhelm Gundel, Sternglaube und Sterndeutung: Die Geschichte und das Wesen der Astrologie , rev. Wilhelm Gundel (Stuttgart, 1931; reprint 1966).

[38] A good case in point is his relationship to his own horoscope—for which see his letter to Cavalcanti in Opera , pp. 732.3–733 (trans. in Letters 2:33–34 [no. 24]), and his letter to Prenninger, Opera , p. 901.2–and his interpretation of Plato's horoscope in his Vita Platonis (cf. Chapter 3, n. 6 above). For the ideal horoscope, see his letter to Lorenzo, Opera , pp. 805.2–806 (trans. in Letters 4:61–63 [no. 46]). Kaske argues that the De Vita was closely associated in Ficino's mind with his own saturnian horoscope: "Introduction," p. 19. See his letter to Filippo Valori of 7 November 1492, Opera , p. 948, and his letter to Pico, Opera , p. 888.

[39] See Chapter 3, n. 1 above.


122

curs at a destined time in the kaleidoscopic cycle of celestial motions, even though, from a philosophical viewpoint, these motions are always in general harmony.[40] To compound the situation, natural sublunar things must themselves arrive at a state of perfect preparation; and there must be a harmonious "accommodation" (coaptatio ) of such a preparation with the stellar and planetary revolutions at the appropriately complementary moment in their cycles. "Fate" is the generic term for the course of the celestials' conjunctions, aspects, and oppositions; and the best, most propitious "effects" are achieved when fate is in accord with, is congruent with, nature. By "effects" Ficino means here the complex of astronomical events—the precise working moment—that prospers or impedes fertility or sterility, that is, the growth or the decay of any sublunar entity or institution. Hence the interplay between what he constantly refers to in traditional terms as the "fatal" and the "natural" law, an interplay that governs our bodies and our feelings, temperaments, mental dispositions, and psychological and social habits (mores ). The larger workings of fate, if known in principle, are therefore unknowable in practice in the sense that their intricacy defies the computational and observational skills of all stargazers, however learned in the lore of Ptolemy's Almagest and Tetrabiblos and their Arab commentators, and likewise of all mathematicians, who gaze upon the stars as a diagrammatic aid to the contemplation of their abstract, their musical and geometrical relationships. The general principle, however, is clear, namely that governing the heavenly machinery are fundamental ratios and harmonies that together constitute a greater harmony, the music of the spheres that an enraptured Pythagoras had heard with his inner ear.41

Ficino introduces, however, a major exception to the theory of man's ignorance of the future, given the appearance in certain ages of "certain divine ingenia ." These ingenia may themselves be the result of a harmonious accord between the conversions of the spheres and the fixed stars and the planetary revolutions, but in any event God bestows on them an intuitive, a prophetic understanding of such accords, which are otherwise known only to Him and are especially ordained by Him. The postulation of such divine ingenia implies a con-

[40] Again cf. Republic 7.529C–531C and of course the Timaeus . Ficino would also have recalled Macrobius's In Sommium Scipionis 2.1.8–13.

[41] See my Platonism , pp. 53–55, and n. 16 above; also Heninger, Touches of Sweet Harmony , pp. 31, 100.


123

ception on Ficino's part not of a quasi-Stoic fortune, let alone of mere chance,[42] giving birth to the "great men" of history, but rather of the God-determined prospering of certain philosopher-theologian-poet-seers at certain times, human intelligences to whom He has granted preternatural, godlike powers. Ficino envisages indeed a kind of apostolic succession of Platonic ingeniosi or theologi , each presiding spiritually over an epoch.

Now the mid Quattrocento had nurtured Ficino himself as a saturnian thinker, as a Plato redivivus in the witty eyes of his contemporaries; and he had labored like a prophet to revive Platonism in Florence—to revive indeed the Pythagoreanism to which Plato had owed his most profound metaphysical and theological debts and which had flourished in the Magna Graecia of ancient Italy as the fruit preeminently of Italic intellect. Nonetheless, I believe Ficino was too diffident and too intelligent to suppose that his own scholarly and pedagogical accomplishments—though to a degree divinely inspired, as friends assured him flatteringly,[43] and though an instrument assuredly of providence[44] —constituted the work of a divinum ingenium , of some new Zoroaster or Hermes inaugurating an epochal rebirth of the spirit. For such a seer would be endowed with an insight into his own destiny centered on the perception of the dominance at last of a perfect number, since the ages that witness the prospering of "certain divine ingenia " are always measured, writes Ficino, by such a number. But is such a number the instrument of fate?

The nuptial and trigon 6 is also the first of a handful of perfect numbers familiar to us, as chapter 17 of the De Numero Fatali de-

[42] For mere chance or fortune, see the letter to Lorenzo Franceschi which opens Ficino's fourth book of Epistulae (Opera , pp. 751.3–752; trans. in Letters 3:3–4): "Denique sive fortuna res nostrae sive fato provenire dicantur, divina providentia irrationalem fortunam in ordinem ratione disponit, immite etiam fatum ad bonum suavissime temperat."

[43] See, for instance, Cavalcanti's letter, now no. 23 in Ficino's fourth book of Epistulae (Opera , p. 732.2), already referred to above in n. 3. Having exhorted Ficino to thank Saturn for his intellectual gifts, Cavalcanti proceeds to remind him of the Herculean strength by which he has made his way through the whole of Greece and even Egypt to bring back the wise men of old on his shoulders: "You have cleansed our eyes of all mists . . . through you this age has looked deeply into those whom Italy had never seen. . . . Will you therefore accuse Saturn, he who purposed that you should rise above other men?" (trans. in Letters 2:32). For a complete list of testimonies to Ficino and his work, see Kristeller, Supplementum 2:204–318, 369–371; and idem, Ficino and His Work , pp. 169–180.

[44] See his notable reply to the accusatory letter of John, the Hungarian. Both are now in the eighth book of his Epistulae (Opera , pp. 871.2–872) and date from the second luster of the 1480s. See n. 24 above.


124

clares, the others being 28, 496 and 8128, the numbers chapter 4 had defined as the products of their own factors.[45] But are any of these the number Ficino has in mind? Presumably all four could somehow be involved in determining the onset and duration of a new era.[46] However, if all four perfect numbers are involved together and not separately, or if various units measured by one such number are superimposed on each other, or if various units measured by all such numbers are in turn superimposed on all the other such units as well as on each other, then once again computing the combinations will become staggeringly complex and testify dramatically to God's omniscience. Moreover, perfect numbers higher than 8128 exist—though Ficino omits any mention of them—which could be factored in ad libitum . Finally, the obvious, equally superhuman, problem confronts us of determining when to begin and end a computation, when to start the numbering of any given span either with a perfect number or with the perfect numbers or indeed with any number. The advent of the perfect number or numbers remains therefore a sublime mystery, and the "perfect" succession of ages that it signifies is known only to God and to the prophet He inspires. It comes as the instrument not of celestial fate but of divine providence, and predicting it defies our mathematical as well as our astrological powers. Again, we are dealing with a different order of magnitude entirely from that confronting the ordinary astrologer, whether his concerns be genethliacal or horary.[47]

We are now in a position to appreciate more fully the aura surrounding Savonarola and something of the enthusiasm, the ambivalence, the hopes, the uncertainties, the fears his apocalyptic vision aroused in the republic, a vision that swept away, incidentally, some of Ficino's closest friends, including Pico. Was this at last an inspired prophet? Would he predict, even as he vehemently attacked the follies of the astrologers, that the numbering of time was approaching perfection, that the governance by one or by all of the perfect numbers

[45] Each is also, we might add, a multiple of increasing powers of 2: of 2(x3), 2 (x7), 2 (x31), 2 (x127).

[46] We should be prepared, I suppose, to interpret them variously, however, in that 496, for instance, could mark the number of centuries, of years, of months, of days, or even conceivably of hours, minutes, and seconds (496 months being 41 1/3 years, 496 hours being 20 2/3 days, and so on).

[47] Since elective or catarchic astrology is oriented towards the constant factors, the unchanging characteristics, of the stars, it is less dependent on their motions and thus on the computation of such motions. This is why one thematic half of the De Vita can ignore the whole question of timing while the other half is obsessed with it. Again see Garin, Lo zodiaco , chapter 2.


125

was now at hand? Or would he point rather towards an imperfect and imperfecting number, or such a number within the fatal number, hanging like a sword over the unhappy age and betokening endless internecine wars and horrendous disasters? Or was he just another in the long line of false prophets who could only lie about the units of God's time for Florence, for the world? Perhaps his uncompromising attack on all astrology was itself a daemonic ruse? Was he the Antichrist? In the event Ficino's sense of betrayal would be shared by a number of his contemporaries and must account, in part at least, for the unworthy and uncharacteristic tone of the condemnatory Apologia which he wrote after the Dominican's fiery execution on 23 May 1498 in the Piazza della Signoria.[48] In the years immediately following the De Numero Fatali 's publication in the December of 1496, the Empedoclean strife of the 1490s would conclude, that is, in a bewilderingly calamitous arithmetic, and not in the longed-for imminence of 6 or 28.

If the complexity and variety of stellar durations and motions had always been the Achilles' heel of astrology as a predictive science, nevertheless a heavenly variety is required, writes Ficino, if we are to measure "the whole life of the world," to measure the multifarious units of duration that govern the sequence of the ages, and the lives of men, their nations, their communities, their institutions, visible and invisible, as well as the lives of all natural entities animate and inanimate alike. Necessarily many units must be less than the century of the saeculum in that they have their own peculiar relationship to the secular age and to each and every other unit that arches into or through or out of it, however small; equally, other units must be greater than the saeculum . The 100, that is, is not the governor of time.

Ficino's second chapter begins indeed with the postulation of many-centuried periods that extend from flood to flood, the cataclysmic markers of the world's history[49] and of the great cycles of "re-

[48] We should align the Apologia with the anti-Savonarolan aspects of Ficino's lectures on Saint Paul, which have been discussed by Father A. F. Verde in his Lo studio fiorentino, 1473–1503: Ricerche e documenti , vol. 4, La vita universitaria (Florence, 1985), pp. 1270–1273. See also Gentile in Mostra , pp. 159–160 (no. 123).

[49] Apart from the Statesman , the most famous Platonic notices of such inundations, and their accompanying conflagrations, are in the Timaeus 22C–23C, Laws 3.677AB (cf. 3.702A), and Critias 109D, 112A (for which see Ficino's epitome, Opera , pp. 1486–1487). See also Aristotle's mention of the Great Winter in his Meteorology 352a28 ff.


126

formation" or cyclical renewal that punctuate or possibly even coincide with the Platonic great year. Here discord is endemic. Just as we suffocate to death whenever the primary ratios of the qualities in us or the air we breathe are disrupted, so the disruption caused by "multiple [grand?] conjunctions in heaven" results in cataclysmic inundations and conflagrations.

The theory that natural disasters are the result of stellar disproportions has a long history, and Ficino is warily echoing an Empedoclean and Stoic commonplace even though it conflicts with his allegiance both to the Plotinian view that the stars in themselves are beautiful and good and to the Pythagorean belief that they circle above us in perpetual harmony.[50] His primary Platonic guide to this theme, however, was the myth about the reversals in the direction of the world's rotation, with their accompanying earthquakes and mass destructions, in the Statesman 268E–274D, a dialogue, significantly, which also focuses on the idea of the perfect state.[51] Notably among the ancients, Proclus in his Platonic Theology 5.6–7 and 25 had labored at its interpretation, though Ficino was to follow him only in part in his epitome for the dialogue, our chief source for his interpretation.[52] In the myth, Ficino writes, Plato opposes the reign of Saturn over the earth-born race to that of Jove over our current generations, and declares that Saturn's was the prior and more blessed. Under Saturn men contemplated the divine, whereas under Jove they have given themselves over to action and to human affairs and pleasure (actio vitaque humana ). The Statesman 's Saturn—and here Ficino refers to the Cratylus 's defi-

[50] See Cavalcanti's letter to Ficino, now the 23d letter in the third book of Ficino's Epistulae (Opera , p. 732.2; trans. in Letters 2:31–32): "By Hercules, the stars can do us no harm; they cannot, I say, because they do not wish to."

[51] We should recall that the Statesman was a sequel to the Sophist and was intended to be a prologue to the Philosopher , which was never written. It foregrounds, that is, the problem of the relationship between philosopher and ruler and suggests, like the Republic , the possibility of an ideal philosopher-king. We should bear in mind Ficino's repeated references to such an ideal in his references to the Medici, to Matthias Corvinus, to friends; and also that he translated the De Monarchia of Dante as a token gesture perhaps to the Ghibelline model of the ideal ruler.

However, in a letter to Cherubino Quarquagli in the third book of his Epistulae (Opera , p. 744; trans. in Letters 2:64–67 [no. 53] at 67), Ficino writes that "a philosopher is a philosopher against the will of the state (civitas ) in which he is born and in spite of its active resistance." This seems to run counter to the role assigned the Platonic guardians in the Republic and to reflect rather the unhappy lot of Socrates in the Apology, Crito, and Phaedo .

[52] Ed. Saffrey and Westerink, 5:24.22–26.20, 91.19–96.24. Ficino's epitome is to be found in his Opera , pp. 1294.4–1296.


127

nition at 396B—"comprehends the purity and inviolable integrity of mind"; and during his reign the divine mind ruled supreme over man, and all his actions were undertaken for the sake of, and in light of, contemplation:

Saturn (Cronos ) is the supreme intellect among the angels by whose rays souls in addition to the angels are illumined and inflamed and are raised continually with all their might to the intellectual life. Whenever souls are converted to this life, they are said to live under Saturn's rule in that they live by the understanding. Consequently, in this life they are said to be regenerated by their own will because they choose to be reformed for the better. Again they are said to grow young again daily (that is, if days can be numbered then) and to blossom more and more. Hence the words of the Apostle Paul, "The inward man is renewed day by day." Finally, fruits are said to be supplied men in abundance, produced unbidden and in a perpetual spring; and this is because there—not by way of their senses and laborious discipline but by way of the inner light—men enjoy to the highest degree the tranquillity of life and pleasure, along with the wonderful spectacles of truth itself.[53]

Jove's rule by contrast appears to be marked by accelerating disorder, mounting chaos.

In the Republic 8.546E ff., however, Plato had introduced, as we

[53] Platonis Opera Omnia (1491) fols. 70v–71r (sig. i[6]v-i[7]r) (i.e., Opera , p. 1296):

Saturnum vero supremum inter angelos intellectum, cuius radiis illustrentur ultra [Op. inter] angelos animae accendanturque et ad intellectualem vitam continue pro viribus erigantur, quae quotiens [Op. quoties] ad vitam eiusmodi convertuntur eatenus sub regno Saturni dicuntur vivere quatenus intelligentia vivunt. Proinde in ea vita ideo sponte dicuntur regenerari quia electione propria in melius reformantur. Rursus in dies reiuvenescere, id est, in dies si modo ibi dies dinumerantur, magis magisque florescere. Hoc illud Apostoli Pauli: Homo interior renovatur in dies. Denique illis alimenta sponte affatim sub perpetuo vere suppeditari quia non per sensus operosamque [Op. operamque] disciplinam, sed per lumen intimum, summaque cum vitae tranquillitate atque voluptate miris veritatis ipsius spectaculis perfruuntur.

The Pauline reference is to 2 Corinthians 4:16 ("is qui intus est renovatur de die in diem"), and the reference to "spectacles" alludes to the Phaedrus 247A4–5 (for Ficino's gloss on which, see my Platonism , p. 151). See Cesare Vasoli, "Juste, justice et loi dans les commentaires de Marsile Ficin," in Le juste et l'injuste à la Renaissance et à l'âge classique , ed. Christiane Lauvergnat-Gagnière and Bernard Yon (Saint-Etienne, 1987), pp. 11–22 at 20–22.

Cf. the passage in the Laws 4.713A ff. on the blessed time of Cronos "of which the best-ordered of existing states is a copy," and in which men were ruled by demigods, daemons, who gave men "peace, reverence, order, and justice never failing" (713DE). Significantly, law is the key to any attempt we might have to recapture that happy life (714A), and law is the domain of Jupiter. Thus the answer to the question posed at 713A—Who is the god who should give his name to the true state?—can be either Cronos or Jupiter or Cronos-Jupiter.


128

have seen, Hesiod's reference in his Works and Days 110–200 to the goodness of the gold and silver ages and to their succession by the degenerate ages of bronze and iron. To juxtapose the two passages is therefore to problematize the rule of Jove: Is his a good reign or a bad? Is his silver age potentially gold or iron?

In the Statesman 's myth our present circuit is from east to west and is jovian and therefore fatal; the contrary, more blessed circuit is from west to east and is saturnian and providential; and this might suggest that the planet Saturn serves as the mediator between the realms governed by planetary fate and the realm governed by providence alone. Since the course of time is thus reversed, old men—or more generally the old world—return to their youth and pass from hoary age to babbling infancy. But we must see this reversal through the eyes of the Neoplatonists, though Ficino does not adopt the radical interpretation proposed in Proclus's Platonic Theology 5.6 and 25. For there Zeus is equated with the "demiurge and father" of the Timaeus 41A7 (on the basis of the Statesman 's own reference at 273B1–2) and adjudged—insofar as "he raises all who exist and turns them back again towards Cronos"—to be the cause of both the reversals in the myth and not just of the reversal that has produced the present fatal age.[54]

In his argumentum for the Statesman , Ficino writes that, while Plato may call "jovian the life of souls in elemental bodies—the life devoted to the senses and to action," yet he calls Jove himself the World-Soul "by whose fatal law the manifest order of the manifest world is arranged."[55] This implies that the fatal numbers, and the proportions that they contain and that govern them, belong to Jove as the World-Soul. At the nadir of the cycle, a conversio will occur and the cycle will be reversed. Underlying the myth, therefore, is the notion of a new "birth" that is at the same time a return. Though the time frame itself is hidden from mortal understandings, still we have an evident disjunction between the artificial hundred-year century cycle and the more fundamental cycles both of fatal and of providential history, a disjunction keyed not only to the two kinds of measures—man's with his 5's and 10's and God's with his 6's and 12's—but to the proportions that govern them. Juxtaposed in effect are

[54] Cf. Hesiod, Works and Days 181 (and in general 110–200).

[55] Platonis Opera Omnia (1491) fol. 70v (sig. i[6]v) (i.e., Opera , p. 1296), "Iovem, ut arbitror, animam mundi vocat, cuius lege fatali manifestus hic manifesti mundi ordo disponitur. Praeterea vitam animorum in corporibus elementalibus ioviam esse vult sensibus actionique deditam."


129

alternative calendars with internal geometric (as well as, presumably, arithmetic and harmonic) ratios; and to superimpose them confronts us with the prospect that at certain rare and extraordinary moments the parameters of these calendars, and the ratios that govern them, will coincide, will mesh together. At such a time, man's inner and outer calendars will be brought back into line with the great star calendar and hence with God's calendar. The measure of man's time will become, for a divinely appointed moment or period, coincident with the measure of cosmic time. And this the prophets alone can predict.

Nevertheless, without being prophets we can at least glimpse something of the basic mathematics involved. In order to approach such huge expanses of cyclical, fatal, and providential time as are called for in the myth in the Statesman , Ficino argues that Plato requires us to multiply "such a perfect number . . . to the numberless," meaning, I take it, to multiply 6 by 100 or its multiples. For chapter 15 metaphorically refers to the 102 , that is, to 100, as the plane of the 10, and to the 10,000, that is, to 1002 , as the "numberless" number. Effectively, however, Ficino thinks of all multiples of 10 as "proceeding" to the numberless, since 10 signifies the universe in its plurality, 102 the universe in its dimensionality, 103 the universe in its solidity and cubicity, 1000 being defined as the "solid" number. Accordingly, by "such a perfect number [proceeding] . . . to the numberless" he probably means 36,000 (i.e., 62 x103 ), the number of the great year.

Moreover, the "parts" of a perfect number measure the forming or "reformation" of lesser public or private durations. An example is 7, a "part" of 28, the second perfect number: just as seven years mark the basic divisions in life—the seven ages of man—so seven days mark the progress of a fever or disease, and seven hours the "lesser mutations" we undergo for good or ill. The reformation is complete when the number "arrives at" 6—meaning I take it when we reach the sixth year (or a multiple of 6)—for then we have reached a perfectly balanced condition, the perfect habitus . When the number arrives at 8 (or a multiple of 8), however, then we are in the opposite condition of deficiency and need, since 8 as a number is deficient in parts, meaning, as chapter 4 makes clear, that its factors add up to a product less than itself—4+2+1=7. Even so, Ficino adds diplomatically, since 8 is 2x2x2, it is a "solid" number—indeed, the first of the solid numbers—and this solidity may serve at times to "balance" or counteract its basic deficiency (in astrology, we might note, the eighth house is the house of death).


130

Perhaps it is coincidental that Ficino chooses to end his commentary on the fatal number with a brief discussion with the astrologers for whom 6 and 62 play such a major role, given the division of the celestial circle into 36 arcs each of 10 degrees, given the dodecade of the zodiacal signs each with three faces, and given the dodecatropos of the mundane houses again divided into three that we establish for an individual astrological chart.[56] However, his choice of 17 as the chapter in which to do this was a witty choice in that 17 is the diagonal number for a square with sides of 12;[57] and the course of the argument, moreover, leads him to address the theme at the root of the entire discussion, namely, the nature of human dependency on, and accord with, the heavens. His vehicle is the polyonymous figure of Jupiter, the planet and the father of gods and men, the philandering deity and the god of law, the Olympian thunderer and the temperer, the august keeper of oaths. For this fatal and yet providential king provides us with the key to an understanding of the power of the perfect numbers and the fatal numbers and their awful interaction.

To Jupiter the ancients had attributed the number 6, the first of the perfect numbers and the geometric mean at the heart of the Platonic lambda, and thus the power to unite human with divine generation, the two themes so obviously juxtaposed by Plato in the Republic 's eighth book. Indeed, although Ficino declares, as we have seen, that the perfect number is known to God alone, yet he proceeds as if it were Jove's number 6 or a multiple of 6.[58] Furthermore, while he seems committed to the notion that 6 is the key to the number of divine generation, and that its double 12 is the key to mortal generation, in fact he has 6 in mind for mortal life as well—the life of individuals as mortals and of mankind as a mortal species (subject to the cycle of 36,000 years). Insofar as Jupiter is the sixth planet, Ficino is

[56] See Kaske, "Introduction," pp. 35–36. The dodecatropos is the result of dividing the ecliptic, numbering downwards from the ascendant on the eastern horizon and thence up from the descendant on the western, into twelve arcs of 30° called the "mundane houses" or plagae . The zodiac is deemed to revolve through this fixed circle (the creation of spherical trigonometry) each plaga of which denotes an area of life: the sixth, for instance, indicates health, the eighth death, the twelfth tribulation.

[57] We might also note that the sum of the first seventeen numbers is 153, the catch of fishes netted by the seven Apostles at the bidding of the risen Christ in John 21:11, as Augustine had pointed out in his Contra Faustum 6; and that 17 is the number of the famous chapter in Revelation on the whore of Babylon seated on the beast with seven heads and ten horns.

[58] The last digits in the four perfect numbers known to Ficino alternate in a 6–8 pattern: that is, perfection and imperfection (in this case deficiency) are contained within perfection.


131

able to sidestep the implications of subordinating all even numbers to all odd numbers as female to male. As the first perfect number, 6 signifies constancy, equality, temperance, and thus the jovian "complexion" in man, a complexion as rare as the perfect number (17.63–67).[59] Six also signifies the "whole harmony of celestials" under the leadership of Jove. Additionally, the powers of 6 identify it as a circular number with 5 and 4 under it, 6 in this context referring to the circuit of the firmament, as 5 to that of the planets, and 4 to that of the elements. This, the complexion of Jupiter himself, is the paradigm, therefore, for heavenly harmony and for its images on earth: the harmony of the perfect republic, of the perfect family, of the perfect marriage, of the perfect procreating and the perfect offspring—"as rare as is the perfection, so rare is the divine progeny" (17.47–48).[60]

Not only are the complexions of the marriage or mating partners keyed to 6 (6 being the first of the nuptial numbers), but so too is the opportunitas for marriage itself, along with the propitiousness of the sixth month of conception and of the sixth year as witnessing the onset of education. The jovian, the perfect 6 is the key for capturing the best auspices, the opportunitas indeed, in any undertaking; for it is neither wanting nor overflowing, neither lacking nor exceeding. Whereas the fatal number is the multiple, writes Ficino, of an abundant number (and not of a deficient, interestingly),[61] the perfect number by contrast is neither abundant nor the offspring of abundance, but constant, tempered, equal—"standing firm in its parts and powers"—and therefore properly the first of the spousal numbers (17.56–62).

In praising Jove as the sixth of the planets from Earth, Ficino also notes that Venus is the sixth planet from the firmament and thus in a way a lesser Jove like Juno, as Plotinus had enigmatically affirmed.[62] In

[59] The De Vita constantly holds Jupiter up as the supremely tempered planet, e.g., 3.5.16–21 (Jove is "wholly tempered in quality . . . and in all things totally in accord [maxime congruentem ] with human nature"), 3.16.114–117.

[60] Ficino surely noticed that Plato's prescription in the Republic 5.454–463 (as he interpreted it in the De Numero Fatali 16)—namely, that men should begin procreating at 30 (5x6) and women at 20 (5x4), and that men's procreating should last 25 years (5x5) and women's 20—plays upon the symbolism of 4, 5, and 6.

[61] Hence the situation is weighted towards fertility, not sterility, though Ficino keeps this as an option.

[62] See Enneads 3.5.3–5 (Venus as the World-Soul, i.e., Jove), 3.5.8 (Venus as Juno); also my Platonism , pp. 130–132. We might also note that, in the PlatonicPorphyrian order, the Sun is sixth from Saturn and the Moon from Jupiter: six governs, that is, the four life-giving planets.


132

addition he addresses the issue of the six's presence in planetary aspects, conjunctions, and oppositions, the most problematic of all being, as we might have anticipated, the conjunctions of Jupiter with Saturn, wherein Jupiter "conciliates" Saturn, who is otherwise "discordant to us."[63] The astrologers had declared that the influence of "such a league" flourishes for twenty years; and within that twenty-year span, Ficino writes, Saturn and Jupiter alternate "perhaps" in exercising sovereign sway over the successive years. Thus we must elect for our best advantage either the time of their conjunction or the alternating jovian years and especially the sixth, twelfth, and eighteenth—the years that are the multiples of 6.[64] Correspondingly, we should elect the sextile aspect of Jove to Saturn or the trine, which is double the sextile, since both aspects represent the "affection" of the 6 and thus of a perfect number.[65]

The jovian virtues, furthermore, are reproduced by the Moon in certain aspects to the Sun: in conjunction (i.e. pre-new Moon, not eclipse),[66] and in sextile and trine aspects. For then the Moon mixes

[63] For the conjunction of Saturn and Jupiter, cf. Ficino's long letter of 6 January 1481 (Florentine style) to Federico, Duke of Urbino, now in the seventh book of his Epistulae (Opera , pp. 849–853). Here he refutes those astrologers who affirm that Christianity arose because of an ordinary conjunction of Saturn and Jupiter on the grounds that such occurs every twenty years, whereas the "grand conjunction," i.e., returning to conjunction in the sign of Aries, takes 960 years (often rounded up to 1000 years). We should bear in mind, however, that the definition of a "grand" conjunction was continually disputed. He goes on to adduce the ninth-century Albumasar's deterministic views (including those on the decan sign in the first face of Virgo); to cite Plotinus's contrary views on the stars as signs, not causes; to take up the theme of the Magi's star; and so forth. See Garin's edition of Pico's Disputationes 1:635–639, with further references; his Lo zodiaco , chapter 1 and passim; and his "Renovatio e 'l'oroscopo delle religioni,'" and "Il 'nuovo secolo' e i suoi annunciatori," both in his La cultura filosofica del Rinascimento italiano (Florence, 1961), pp. 155–158 and 224–228.

[64] One wonders whether Ficino charted his own intellectual biography on the basis of such jovian predominances. See his letter to Giovanni Niccolini, Archbishop of Amalfi, in the fifth book of his Epistulae (trans. in Letters 4:60–61 [no. 45]), where he declares, "I have long wanted to live my life with someone of a jovian nature, so that something of a bitter, and, as I might say, saturnian element, which either my natal star has bestowed on me or which philosophy has added, might eventually be alleviated."

[65] The aspects refer to the planets' distances from each other as measured by degrees of the heavenly arc; they are defined by Ficino in his De Vita 3.4.66–69, 3.10.34–36. Ptolemy observes in the Tetrabiblos 1.13 that of the four aspects "the trine [120° apart] and the sextile [60° apart] are called harmonious because they are composed of zodiacal signs of the same kind, either entirely female or entirely male; while the square [90° apart] and the opposite [180° apart] are discordant because they are composed of signs of opposite kinds." See too Ficino's letter to Bernardo Bembo in the third book of his Epistulae (Opera , p. 722.2; trans. in Letters 2:7 [no. 2]).

[66] Conjunction can mean that one planet is eclipsing another (a rare occurrence),

or is on the same celestial longitude with it, or is in the process of traversing it within a certain number of degrees (called the "orb"). A planet so close to the Sun as to be invisible is said to be "combust." See Kaske, "Introduction," pp. 34–35.


133

its qualities temperately with those of the Sun and presides over the six-associated qualities of Jove: temperance, constancy, firmness. We are dealing, if you will, with the Moon's jovian aspects. Ficino is bolstered in this speculation by its association with 12, the first of the abundant numbers, since the Moon waxes in twelve days and wanes in the same. Thus for the best offspring we should beget only when the Moon is waxing; and perhaps on only six of those twelve waxing days. For Ficino speculates that the Moon and Sun must share the rule in the days of waxing by alternating as Saturn and Jupiter do over the years. Thus the Moon would possess the second day after the union (i.e., the conjunction) with the Sun, each tempering the other. Again, presumably, the sixth and the twelfth days are especially favorable.[67] The Moon endows things subject to fate with the second perfection, as we have seen, since 28 is the second perfect number as well as the number of days in the month.

All these aspects governed by 6 must be uncovered and analyzed "with all our strength" if we are to acquire temperance in ourselves and a stable prosperity in our spirits and in our bodies. After we have acquired this prosperous temperance, and only then, will we be in a position to devote ourselves to saturnian contemplation. This is an important proviso that weakens the force of Panofsky, Saxl, and Klibansky's analysis in Saturn and Melancholy , as we have seen.[68] For it is the jovian man preeminently who can approach the contemplative life of Saturn, since the jovian man is the perfectly tempered or complexioned man, as the De Vita had insisted despite its preoccupation with the unique capacities, indebtedness, and problems of the saturnian scholar.[69] Ficino exhorts us to make ready our ingenia under jovian

[67] We should bear in mind that the Moon returns to the same point of the zodiac every 28 days, but to the Sun every 29—a fact Ficino sees Plato alluding to in the Republic 9 at 587E–588A (see De Numero Fatali 3.3). The mean for the lunar synodic month, incidentally, is 29.53059 days.

[68] See Chapter 3, n. 6 above. Other studies of Renaissance melancholy have understandably used Saturn and Melancholy as their starting point and thus misrepresented Ficino's complex position on the role of Saturn. In general see now Massimo Ciavolella and Amilcare A. Iannucci, eds., Saturn from Antiquity to the Renaissance (Ottowa, 1992).

[69] If you insist, as Ficino does in the De Vita at 3.12.107–109, that mensura is the first universal principle, then the preeminence of Jove as the supremely measured deity logically follows. Whatever Saturn's gifts, Ficino always viewed Saturn and his influence as extreme and in need of being tempered by Jove (Iuppiter ipse, Saturni temperies ); see, for instance, 3.22.18–44, 59–83.


134

auspices, so that "whenever" the saturnian ages return—meaning the times of golden contemplation—they themselves may be instantly transformed into silver and gold. This is a cautious statement, however, that conceals Ficino's belief, and notably here in the De Numero Fatali , that this "whenever" can only be predicted and then expedited by "certain divine men" endowed by God with a visionary insight into the providential and the fatal orders and their concordant interaction.

While the Statesman 's myth of the golden age privileges Saturn over Jupiter and depicts the jovian age as a fatal, increasingly discordant self-piloting (273C), the time when God has let go the world and no longer guides it in its course (269C), Ficino, like Proclus, could not accept this at face value, given Plotinus's decision on several occasions to identify the providential Zeus both with the World-Soul and with the World-Mind, and thus effectively to equate, or at least accommodate, the aged father and the Olympian son.[70] At the heart of what Ficino predictably sees as a mystery is the notion again of conceptual parallax: what is superior from one perspective is inferior from another and yet each perspective is valid; the parts must be seen in the context of the whole. Thus Jupiter and Saturn become complementary figures, become aspects of each other; they are the father-in-the-son of the Hermetic mystery, which, from Ficino's point of view, Plato, Plotinus, Iamblichus, and all the Platonici had inherited from Egypt.[71]

To penetrate fully to this synthetic vision, we must return as interpreters to the golden age of saturnian contemplation. But for our vision to be universal and lasting, we must await the return of that age in present time, in something more, that is, than the imagination's prospect or the memory's retrospection. Indeed, the power of the myth of the golden age over Ficino and his Medicean contemporaries lay in the belief that it might be made actually to come again; that it

[70] See my Platonism , pp. 123–129, 138, 144–156, 193–194, 238–240. One of the primary texts for the Neoplatonists was the reference in the Philebus at 30D: "And in the divine nature of Zeus would you not say that there is the soul and the mind of a king?" This they interpreted to mean that Jove was both the World-Soul and Mind, the third and the second of the Plotinian hypostases, or powers within these hypostases.

[71] See Ficino's adversion to the great "mystery" concerning the son and the father in Iamblichus's De Mysteriis 6.2 (ed. E. Des Places [Paris, 1966], pp. 195–196) in his epitome for book 6 of the Republic (Opera , p. 1408). As for the references to the father and the son in the Corpus Hermeticum , treatises 1, 10, and 12 would have been particularly significant for Ficino. See my "Marsilio Ficino, Hermes, and the Corpus Hermeticum ," in New Perspectives on Renaissance Thought , ed. John Henry and Sarah Hutton (London, 1990), pp. 38–47 at 42–43, 45–47.


135

could be reinvoked and captured from the heavens by certain "divine" or "daemonic" men who would effectively be magicians over, as well as prophets of, time. However, for this to happen, such men would have to call upon Jove, even if they themselves were saturnian. In order to reunite the two primal progenitors in the mind's eye as a unitary Jove-in-Saturn, and to recreate both the original and the final perfective union in ourselves of the realms of Soul and of Intellect, we must wait upon the jovian action of such saturnian men, invoke and await the coming of thinker-rulers. When the saturnian "shepherds" of time, the demi-gods, from the Statesman 's great myth, are born again, then "the ends of the ages" will dawn with them, the dies novissimi .[72] And yet these shepherds will come and transform the jovian world—guide idyll into epic and epic into idyll—only at Jove's command.

In Ficino's syncretistic hermeneutics this command will coincide with Jove's decision to begin the cosmic cavalcade, in the Phaedrus 's myth of the charioteer, back towards saturnian contemplation: to release, if you will, Saturn from his captivity within the active jovian soul. It is indeed the Jove of the charioteer myth at 247C–248A—the myth that Proclus too had invoked in the same context in his Platonic Theology 5.25, though again his interpretation is different from Ficino's[73] —that enables Ficino to resolve the mystery of the Statesman 's apparently absolute dichotomy between the halcyon reign of Saturn and the tumultuous reign of his usurping youngest son. For Jove, not Saturn, holds the key to the instauration of the golden age: from him comes the divine decision to reverse the disorder of an iron time, to spin the rotation of the world towards the east. For Jove as the Orphic fragment declares is the first, the last, the head and the center, and all things are created and provided for by him,[74] including

[72] Cf. Laws 4.713A–714B, Critias 109BC, and–on the testimony of Ficino's De Vita 3.22.45–51—the Phaedo 110B–111C; also Cratylus 397E–398C (on the men of Hesiod's golden age as being "daemons," meaning knowing and wise).

[73] See my Platonism , pp. 249–255 and passim.

[74] Kern fr. 21a. This shorter version of the "Hymn to Jove" (Kern fr. 168) was familiar to Ficino from [Pseudo-]Aristotle's De Mundo 7.401a28–b7 and was referred to by Plato in his Laws 4.715E (as the De Mundo itself goes on to suggest at b24 ff.) and by Eusebius in his De Praeparatione Evangelica 3.9. One of its first appearances in Ficino's work is in the De Divino Furore of 1457 (ed. Gentile, p. 27; cf. n. 16 above), where it is juxtaposed with the famous line from Vergil's third Eclogue , "Ab Iove principium Muse, Iovis omnia plena" (60), and with Lucan's line in the Pharsalia , "Iupiter est quodcunque vides, quocunque moveris" (9.580). Gentile's apparatus identifies a number of quotations in Ficino's first book of letters that have hitherto escaped us (the line from Lucan being an example); see also his "In margine," 60 ff.


136

the intelligible time that is the image of eternity, even of Saturn's eternity.

Perhaps it was inevitable that Ficino should turn for his envoy to the most authoritative of all the magician-prophet-poets of time in the Latin-Italic tradition, to Vergil who had sung of the philosopher-king Aeneas and his jovian wanderings to the land of Saturnus, and had prepared himself to do so by singing of the golden world of the pastoral, of the piping shepherds and their wandering flocks. For at the heart of Ficino's vision of Platonic eschatology is the yearning for the dawning of another, of an idyllic, an intelligible time. Predictably this moved him to cite from the famous prophecy in the Fourth Eclogue that trumpets forth that "The great order is born from the whole of the generations."[75] With the new order of time, the "last age of the Cumaean song," men themselves will beget a new and more perfect progeny, a progeny of golden wits who will restore the golden age not of Saturn alone but of Saturn and of Jupiter in beneficent conjunction. The jovian decision to restore the golden age is therefore bound up with the notion of progeny, of the decision to beget a new son. And Jove, not Saturn, is the begetting deity of the poets' prurient and copious imaginations.

One might say that Vergil's Fourth Eclogue is a soteriological restatement for Ficino of Plato's enigmatic passage on the fatal number. Certainly, the Vergilian citation helped him to understand the profoundly prophetic cast of that passage, from which Plato emerges as a consummate numerologist, arithmologist, and astrologer, a Greek Isaiah prophesying the coming of a new birth, of a more perfect progeny, of a golden saturnian king of the gods and men, of a maguschild whose name shall be called wonderful.[76] In terms of the

[75] For a survey and bibliography of Christian interpretations of this prophecy—it was cited, for instance, by Statius in Dante's Purgatorio 22.70–72—see Pierre Courcelle, "Les exégèses chrétiennes de la Quatrième Éclogue," Revue des études ancinnes 59 (1957), 294–319. For Vergil's medieval reputation, see the classic study by Domenico Comparetti, Virgilio nel medio evo , rev. Giorgio Pasquali, 2 vols. (Florence, 1937); and Henri de Lubac, L'exégèse médiévale: Les quatre sens de l'Écriture , 4 vols. (Paris, 1959–1964), 2:233–262. For later, see Vladimir Zabughin, Vergilio nel Rinascimento italiano (Bologna, 1921).

[76] Ficino's sense of Plato as a prophet was reinforced by the Second Letter at 314A, to which he refers, for instance, in a letter to Cardinal Bessarion now in the first book of his Epistulae (ed. Gentile, pp. 35–36; trans. in Letters 1:52–53): "Hoc vaticinatus Plato: fore tempus multa post secula, regi Dionysio inquit, quo theologie mysteria exactissima discussione velut igne aurum purgarentur" (12.23–25). See too his Commentary on Saint Paul, chapter 3 (Opera , p. 431.1).


137

Christian-Neoplatonic interpretation that was Ficino's goal, it had been Jove's decision to beget a new son that will ensure eventually the return paradoxically of Saturn's, of the father's, age of gold. We can now see why Ficino and others had trouble with any straightforward accommodation of the Greek mythological generational triad of Uranus-Saturn-Jove with the Christian Trinity. In particular Saturn and Jove were only partially identifiable with the Son and the Holy Spirit, and Ficino had already expressed reservations in his Phaedrus Commentary 10 and 11 about identifying Uranus with the Father even as he had utilized Plotinian and Proclian conceptions to postulate a triple Jupiter.[77] In the event, attributes were transferred and Jove became the Father in his omnipotence, omniscience, and omnipresence, despite Augustine's strident arguments against such an accommodation.[78] Hence for Renaissance Platonists in search of a pagan symbol for the Son the attraction of the candidacy of Hercules, a candidacy first seriously mooted in antiquity and prevalent in the later Middle Ages, and one that reached its apogee in the sixteenth century in Ronsard's ode to Odet de Coligny, "Hercule Chrestien," in his second book of hymns.[79] "The bravest of the gentiles," in Ficino's words,[80] and a son of Jove, Hercules had duly accomplished the greatest of worldly labors and been translated, after an agonizing death occasioned by a centaur's hatred and the venomous blood of the Hydra, into a constellation: a mortal man, he had been made into an immortal god.[81]

Like the Hebrew prophets, possessed of a Mosaic but not yet a Christian wisdom, Plato had predicted the dawning of a new dispensation, the advent of a truly theological philosophy that would supersede his own, the gift of an heroic strength that would defeat the

[77] Ed. Allen, pp. 110–129, esp. 110–115, 118–119, 128–129. See my Platonism , chapters 5 and 6, esp. pp. 119–120, 123–128, 152–155. In his Platonic Theology 5.6, 25, Proclus had maintained that the Statesman was about the "greatest" of the Joves.

[78] De Civitate Dei 4.11. In general see Kristeller, Philosophy of Ficino , pp. 168–169, and my "Absent Angel," pp. 227–228.

[79] See Marcel Simon, Hercule et le christianisme (Paris, 1955).

[80] Opera , pp. 800.2–801; trans. in Letters 4:49 [no. 34]—a letter to Cardinal Riario.

[81] And Ficino frequently calls to mind the haunting lines in Boethius's Consolatio at 4.7.32–35 which conclude "superata tellus sidera donat"—lines that were apparently very familiar to the Renaissance humanists. See my "Homo ad Zodiacum: Marsilio Ficino and the Boethian Hercules," in Forma e parola: Studi in memoria di Fredi Chiappelli , ed. Dennis J. Dutschke, Pier Massimo Forni, Filippo Grazzini, Benjamin R. Lawton, and Laura Sanguineti White (Rome, 1992), pp. 205–221.


138

Hydra of desire and sin. And his insights as a geometer had enabled him to see that the golden age would dawn under the presidency of both the perfect and the fatal numbers; that a child of Zeus would be born to preside over time's perfect measure, over the jovian decision to renew the saturnian measure of the Statesman 's myth. But, despite his "trinitarian" enigmas in the second and sixth Letters and his suggestive wording in the Timaeus about a triple causality, Plato had not foreseen, could not have foreseen clearly, the dogma itself of the Trinity, of the threefold consubstantiality in which the Son is one with the Father and the Father's Spirit.[82] For no pagan filiatory myth of Uranus, Saturn, and Jove, however Orphically or Platonically unfolded, however sympathetically interpreted by a Christian allegorist, could ever do more than dimly adumbrate the unique, the mystical relationship of the three persons in one substance which is the very God not of the philosophers but of revelation.[83]

One of the Bible's most famous triple formulations serves Ficino, appropriately, as his point of closure, the phrase from the Wisdom of Solomon 11:20 [21] that God the Creator has arranged all things in "number, weight, and measure."[84] The implication here is not only

[82] See Wind, Pagan Mysteries , pp. 241–244, and my "Marsilio Ficino on Plato, the Neoplatonists and the Christian Doctrine of the Trinity," Renaissance Quarterly 37 (1984), 555–584. On Ficino's fascination in general with Biblical prophecy, and with the theme of the Second Coming and the dies novissimi , see Cesare Vasoli, "Per le fonti del 'De Christiana Religione' di Marsilio Ficino," Rinascimento , 2d. ser., 28 (1988), 135–233 at 139–141.

[83] Hence Ficino's guarded words on Plotinus, along with Plato his acknowledged master: "Plotinus Apostoli Ioannis et Pauli mysteria saepe tangit, mysterium tamen Trinitatis non tam assecutus videtur quam perscrutatus et pro viribus imitatus" (Opera , p. 1770.1; cf. pp. 1714.2, 1757. 1758.8, 1761.3, 1766.1).

Nonetheless, he asserts towards the end of the fifth chapter of his Commentary on Saint Paul that Socrates and Plato, along with the Gospel (i.e., Christ, as Ficino goes on to determine), had all improved on the Mosaic law: "Item legem Mosaicam, quasi non penitus absolutam sed pro capacitate suscipientium datam, non solum Dominus in Evangelio emendavit sed Socrates etiam atque Plato" (Opera , p. 434). This suggests that the Platonici , in some areas at least, are more important than the Law, if not than the Prophets. For a list of the Platonici 's theological achievements, see the second chapter of his Commentary on Saint Paul (Opera , p. 430.1).

[84] See Appendix 3 below. For God as Himself the measure in Ficino, see the important article by Edward P. Mahoney, "Metaphysical Foundations of the Hierarchy of Being according to Some Late-Medieval and Renaissance Philosophers," in Philosophies of Existence, Ancient and Modern , ed. Parviz Morewedge (New York, 1982), pp. 165–257 at 189–192; idem, "Neoplatonism, the Greek Commentators, and Renaissance Aristotelianism," in Neoplatonism and Christian Thought , ed. Dominic J. O'Meara (Albany, N.Y., 1982), pp. 169–177 and 264–282 at 174–176; idem, "Lovejoy and the Hierarchy of Being," Journal of the History of Ideas 48 (1987), 211–230 at 224.


139

that the world has been created and organized on mathematical principles—preeminently for Ficino as we have reiterated, as for anyone in the Pythagorean tradition, a matter of ratios and proportions—but also that God has disposed time itself in order. A truly divinely inspired prophet is able to hear, if only in passing, the harmonies governing this order and therefore to predict and to invoke the ends and beginnings of new eras and epochs, of other dispensations, of restitutory cycles for nations, for families, for individuals, for the works and deeds of men. Among the prophets of the Gentiles, as Augustine had personally testified, Plato was preeminent.[85] He was the philosopher-theologian who had inherited the prophetic powers of Hermes Trismegistus, of Orpheus, of Sibyls such as Diotima of Mantinea, and whose prophecies could be set beside, if subordinated to, those of Balaam, of Isaiah, of Malachi, of Micah and Zechariah, as bearing witness to the future advent of Christ, of the Platonic Adam, of the Idea of Man.[86] For Christ was to come as the new star in the astrology of ancient belief, the new anima mundi of the old philosophers, the Son divinely begotten at the conjunction of the fatal, the providential, and the nuptial numbers known only to his Father.

We have been granted intimations too of a time when once again man's nuptial and fatal numbers will be governed by the perfect numbers, when both occasion and opportunity will be married to eternity, and mankind married to the Lamb, the bride of the universal Church to the Son whose countenance is as Lebanon, excellent as the cedars. Although it receives no mention in this commentary, Solomon's Canticle of Canticles, as the great biblical text on amatory union, must surely have subtly conditioned Ficino's reading of the crucial passages in Plato's Republic and Laws on the ideal marriage and the ideal off-

[85] For Augustine's praise of Plato see Ficino's remarks in his Vita Platonis sub "Quae Plato affirmavit et qui eum confirmaverunt" (Opera , pp. 769.3–770.1; trans. in Letters 3:45); he refers to the Contra Academicos 3.20.43, De Vera Religione 4.7, Confessions 7.9, and the City of God 2.14.

[86] The Idea of Man was raised as an issue by Plato in the Parmenides 130C1–2. This was commented upon particularly by Proclus in his In Parmenidem 3.812 ff. (ed. Cousin; trans. Glenn R. Morrow and John M. Dillon [Princeton, 1987], pp. 176–177) and then by Ficino in his own Parmenides Commentary 4 (Opera , p. 1139), Ficino being indebted, in part at least, to William of Moerbeke's highly literal Latin translation of Proclus's commentary done around 1285 (ed. Carlos Steel, 2 vols. [Louvain and Leiden, 1982–1985]). Indeed as the logos, the verbum Dei , Christ is the Idea of all things, as the De Christiana Religione explicitly argues. See also Ficino's letter to Cavalcanti on the theory of the Ideas according to the Timaeus (ed. Gentile, pp. 82–85 [no. 42]; trans. in Letters 1:85–88 [no. 43]) and his Commentary on Saint Paul's Epistle to the Romans, chapter 5 (Opera , pp. 433.2–435).


140

spring.[87] For his eugenics are keyed, not to the renewal of some peninsular successor of an ancient Greek city-state, but to the peopling of the future City of God into which all the cities of men, liberated from the sway of fatal numbers, will be at last transformed, Rome on its seven hills having become the New Jerusalem. In Ficino's interpretation, in any Christian Platonist's interpretation, it is the New Jerusalem of Ezekiel and the other Prophets, of St. John on Patmos, and of St. Augustine's greatest work that constitutes the ideal Platonic polis, the city of the Savior. The enigmatic passage in the Republic 's eighth book was thus a gentile's prophecy, seen through a glass darkly, concerning the grafting of the limb of perfection onto the fatal numbering of the Jesse tree of the world, the breeding from the fatal stock of Adam's progeny of a second Adam, of the ideally tempered Man.

If these speculative possibilities were running at all in Ficino's mind, did Plato's passage also evoke various pictorial images associated with the familiar theme of the Annunciation, the moment of Christ's conception and golden begetting, the entry of the perfect jovian numbers into the calculations and computations of the starled wizards from the East?[88] And did Gabriel, the angel of that Annunciation, take on some of the attributes of a Platonic geometermagus in proclaiming the descent of such numbers not only into our soul's planar triangularity but into the regular solids constituted from the triangles of Plato's Timaeus , the solidity, the cubicity of the material creation that bore within it still the vestiges of the Trinity?[89] Was God's divine purpose a kind of spiritual eugenics and the providential course of history the story of how man had been taught through the mystery of the Incarnation to breed the best men, the best deeds, the

[87] See his Phaedrus Commentary 2 (ed. Allen, p. 79), and his letter to Cosimo on Lorenzo Pisano's commentary on Canticles, which is now in the first book of his Epistulae (ed. Gentile, p. 29 [no. 7]; trans. in Letters , 1:48–49 [no. 8]); see also my Platonism , p. 64 and note.

[88] Of course, one of the disputed issues in casting a horoscope, including the horoscope of Christ, is whether to start with the moment of birth or of conception. The latter may have been more astrologically satisfactory but was harder to come by for the obvious reasons of discretion or modesty. It would be idle to speculate about which paintings of the Annunciation would recur to Ficino, given the wealth of possibilities on the walls of late-Quattrocento Florence. Jupiter's ravishment of Danae in a shower of gold is one of the obvious parallels from pagan theology.

[89] Augustine's De Trinitate 9–15 served to justify on theological grounds Ficino's Neoplatonic philosophical and methodological fascination with triads. In general, see Wind, Pagan Mysteries in the Renaissance , pp. 37n, 41–44, 241–255; also Chapter 2, n. 62 above.


141

best thoughts, the best souls; taught to model all his endeavors after the supreme breeding achievement, the generation of the Son of Man? In which case, was Christ's conception and Christ's birth presided over by the nuptial, the fatal, and the perfect numbers in unique accord? And had this accord been symbolized by the new star in the East, as Balaam had foretold in Numbers 24:17, a comet that had been condensed from the air and illuminated by Gabriel, and that had led the Magi, the philosopher-king-geometers, the "wisest of the Chaldaeans," to the crib of a perfectly tempered child, the perfect Timaean triangle, all music's diapason?[90] And when would this accord recur?

Gabriel as a geometer or as a Platonic magistrate determining the best breeding time for Mary, Christ as the ideal citizen of Plato's Republic , the babe in the manger as the triangle or the lambda of the Timaeus , the Savior as a number which is the sum of its parts, these and the other figures and formulations I have just invoked by way of rhetorical questions may be difficult initially for us to credit as being either relevant or sound. Nonetheless, the issues they raise concerning the themes of the immaculate conception, the perfect birth, and the pleroma are in line with those raised by Ficino's many other bold attempts to arrive at an accommodation between Platonism and Christianity, between Pallas and Themis, philosophia and pietas , an accommodation whose principles he always adhered to with unwavering enthusiasm.[91] Indeed, the chiliastic and messianic energies that swirled around the unaccommodating Savonarola in the 1490s must themselves have contributed to his championship here of Plato, the last in the hexadic (the jovian?) succession of ancient theologians, as the culminating prophet in pagan antiquity of rebirth and renovation, of a spiraling ascent into eternity and not just a cyclical return.[92] Mani-

[90] Ficino's sermon, De Stella Magorum , and his Apologia (Opera , pp. 489–491, 572–574) focus on Gabriel's role in creating the comet (the star) that led the magi to Bethlehem rather than on the conception; see Rab Hatfield, "The Compagnia de' Magi," Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes 33 (1970), 107–161; Stephen M. Buhler, "Marsilio Ficino's De Stella Magorum and Renaissance Views of the Magi," Renaissance Quarterly 43.2 (1990), 348–371, with further references; and in general J. L. Jervis, Cometary Theory in Fifteenth-Century Europe (Wroclaw, 1985).

[91] See Cesare Vasoli, Filosofia e religione nella cultura del Rinascimento (Naples, 1988), pp. 19–73; idem, "Ficino e il 'De Christiana Religione,'" in Die Philosophie im 14. und 15. Jahrhundert: In Memoriam Konstanty Michalski (1879–1947) ), ed. Olaf Pluta (Amsterdam, 1988), pp. 151–190.

[92] For the diffusion of chiliastic and Joachimite conceptions in the late Quattrocento and early Cinquecento, see, for example, Marjorie Reeves, Influence of Prophecy

in the Later Middle Ages: A Study in Joachimism (Oxford, 1969), pp. 185 ff.; Ottavia Niccoli, Profeti e popolo nell'Italia del Rinascimento (Rome and Bari, 1987)—this has been translated by Lydia G. Cochrane as Prophecy and People in Renaissance Italy (Princeton, 1990); and the essays by various hands in Prophetic Rome in the High Renaissance Period , ed. Marjorie Reeves (Oxford, 1992) (this includes a comprehensive bibliography). Awaiting investigation, however, is Ficino's own relationship to Franciscan eschatology and Joachimism, and notably to the prophecies concerning the imminent third Age of the Spirit and the middle of three Advents of Christ, for which see Reeves, Influence , pp. 140–144, 198–199. But we can say that, in the 1490s at least, he was not promoting any particular imperial, papal or Medicean candidate as the key to inaugurating the golden age, the Platonic republic, or the New Jerusalem.


142

festly, none of the dialogues spoke more eloquently to this annunciatory theme, and to the theme of the providentially ordered, the ideal commonwealth, than the ten books of the Republic . And no book within it spoke with more esoteric wisdom than the eighth, the book of the great fatal number that ended in the second perfect number that itself ended in 8, the number of death, deficiency and solidity and yet the measure of the octave. In the face both of Savonarola's fulminations against the vanity of pagan learning and philosophy and of the ebbing away of faith in Ficino's whole apologetic enterprise on the part of some of his closest friends, Ficino remained stubbornly and still ardently committed to apology: to the unequivocal promotion of the accommodating argument that Solomon's Jehovah was Plato's Idea of the Good who had arranged all things, including surely the books of the philosopher, in number, weight, and measure. The De Numero Fatali , we recall, was the last of his Platonic commentaries, but it has the same undiminished faith in the validity of the ancient mysteries for a Christian as the De Amore of his youth.


143

Epilogue

"sed medulla"


Ficino was always convinced, as he says in his epitome for the tenth book of the Republic , that a wonderful power lay hidden in the depth of Plato's words, though few were in a position to understand this power.[1] Even so, he remained bewildered in commenting on this eighth book by Plato's impenetrable play, by the "solemn mockery" of the "lofty tragic vein" in which his Muses had jested with us there as if we were children (545DE). And yet it was but another example of the jocose seriousness that often accompanied Plato's sublime method of philosophizing and that Ficino had done his best to emulate in his letters if not in his commentaries. In his argumentum for the Cratylus he observes that "the gods occasionally jest and play. For we jest about matters divine, and the gods jest about our human matters . . . and Plato declares that man himself is the jest and plaything of the gods."[2] Given this divine humor, it was important, Ficino knew, not to allegorize too minutely, too rigidly, too scholastically; for this had been the shortcoming of Proclus for all his brilliance as

[1] Opera , p. 1430: "Arbitror equidem in Platonis verbis vim quandam latere mirabilem a paucissimis intellectam."

[2] Opera , p. 1313: "Addit et deos [Op. Deus] interdum iocariac ludere. Iocamur quidem nos circa divina, iocantur et dii circa nostra. . . . Mitto in praesentia Platonicum illud: Homo iocus est ludusque deorum" (the reference is to the Laws 1.644DE and 7.803C, 804B); cf. pp. 1129, 1137. Cf. Chapter 1, n. 30 above.


144

the last Successor. In another argumentum , that for the Critias , he recalls that "people who try to accommodate all the individual details too precisely (ad unguem ) to the allegory are the objects of Plato's own laughter"; and that in the exordium to the Phaedrus , under the mask of Socrates, Plato had indeed mocked "those who allegorize too curiously in such matters."[3]

In the final analysis, the understanding of God's time is uniquely important to the understanding of the life of man on earth, but at the same time it is "inexplicable," in the literal sense that it cannot be fully "unfolded." His providence may be indeed apprehended intermittently in history, personal or national, but never wholly comprehended by any "blend" of reasoning or experience on the part of the guardians, however wise, however well educated (546AB). It was therefore perhaps appropriate that this mathematical enigma concerning divine and mortal time was the only Platonic enigma whose full solution still eluded Marsilio, even after his long years of scholarly and interpretative apprenticeship. Nonetheless, he was fervently convinced that it spoke to the same profoundly Mosaic mystery that the Prophets had also referred to when they declared with Habakkuk that God had "stood and measured the earth" (3:6), and with Isaiah that He had "measured the waters in the hollow of his hand, and meted out heaven with the span, and comprehended the dust of the earth in a measure and weighed the mountains in scales, and the hills in a balance" (40:12). If Ficino was in no position to follow his brother Platonist Pico della Mirandola into the arcana of cabalistic gematria with its substitutions,[4] let alone into a fully numerological exposition on cabalistic lines of the Hebrew narration of the six days of Creation, still such intellectual consequences were the next logical steps: Pico's marvelous Heptaplus is in the long medieval tradition of the hexaemeral commentary, but it is also a Platonic companion piece, I suggest, for the De Numero Fatali .

Despite our own apprenticeship at the feet of such distinguished interpreters of the mentalité of Renaissance Platonism as Eugenio Garin and Frances Yates, we still tend to dismiss such abandoned and otiose

[3] Opera , p. 1485.2: "Quos equidem, ne si conentur singula allegoriae ad unguem accommodare ab ipso Platone derideantur in exordio Phaedri curiosas nimium in huiusmodi rebus allegorias sub persona Socratis irridente." See my "The Second Ficino-Pico Controversy: Parmenidean Poetry," pp. 446–448, 453–454; and Hankins, Plato in the Italian Renaissance 1:337–339, 344–345.

[4] See Chaim Wirszubski, Pico della Mirandola's Encounter with Jewish Mysticism (Cambridge, Mass., 1989), pp. 117, 172–173.


145

disciplines as magic and astrology as somehow "foreign" to what is most significant and most characteristic about that Platonism. The same is true, a fortiori , for arithmology and mystical geometry, particularly since they are even more unfamiliar to the majority of historians in the field. However, I hope I have now demonstrated that without some acquaintance with Ficino's work in this area, we can appreciate fully neither the complex achievement of his revival of Plato in the Quattrocento nor the multifaceted impact of that revival on the thought and consciousness of his European contemporaries. For the Commentary on the Fatal Number is his principal attempt to unfold the mystery at the heart of Platonic mathematics and to address the prophetic themes he associated with that mystery. As such it provides us with a unique perspective on his visionary philosophy and on the blend of ancient authorities which contributed to the breadth and intricacies of its formulation.


147

PART ONE STUDY
 

Preferred Citation: Allen, Michael J. B. Nuptial Arithmetic: Marsilio Ficino's Commentary on the Fatal Number in Book VIII of Plato's Republic. Berkeley:  University of California Press,  c1994 1994. http://ark.cdlib.org/ark:/13030/ft6j49p0qv/