Preferred Citation: Krueger, Derek. Symeon the Holy Fool: Leontius's Life and the Late Antique City. Berkeley:  University of California Press,  c1996 1996. http://ark.cdlib.org/ark:/13030/ft6k4007sx/


 
Diogenes in Late Antiquity

5. Diogenes in Late Antiquity

In many ways, the Life of Symeon the Fool conforms to patterns for narrating the lives of holy men in Late Antiquity. The broad outlines of the text share much with more widely studied Late Antique saints’ lives, such as Athanasius’s Life of Antony, Theodoret’s portrait of Symeon the Stylite, or the Life of Theodore of Sykeon. Even Symeon’s antics can be understood both as a reversal of ascetic practice and as thematically related to stories of secret sanctity found in a number of earlier Christian texts. The magnitude of Symeon’s shameless behavior, however, is distinctive, and precedents for the playful, even burlesque elements in the text warrant further exploration. If the canons of Christian hagiography do not fully provide a context for understanding Symeon’s shamelessness, what elements of Late Ancient culture do? The Greco-Roman Cynic tradition provides part of the answer.

Diogenes of Sinope lived in Athens during the fourth century BCE. According to the account given by Diogenes Laertius in his Lives of the Philosophers, the Cynic tradition started with Antisthenes, a student of Socrates. The movement gained notoriety with Antisthenes’ disciple, Diogenes, an exile from Sinope, a city on the Black Sea coast of Asia Minor. Although the colorful anecdotes reported about Diogenes in the Lives of the Philosophers and other ancient writings are of little value for reconstructing the life of the historical Diogenes of Sinope,[1] the tradition tended to portray him walking the streets, dressed in a philosopher’s robe, carrying a wallet and a staff. He upbraided passersby for their hypocrisy, and from time to time he performed deeds considered shocking: eating in the market or at public lectures, farting loudly in crowded places, urinating, masturbating, and even defecating wherever he chose.[2]

The parallels between Symeon and Diogenes are striking. As we shall see in the next chapter, Leontius carefully models Symeon’s behavior on that attributed to this Cynic philosopher in both pagan and Christian lore. In order to understand the significance of the connection between Symeon the Fool and Diogenes the Cynic, however, we must leave Symeon aside for the moment and consider the place of Diogenes in Christian intellectual history.[3] Therefore, this chapter considers the attitudes of Christian writers from the second half of the fourth century to the early seventh century toward traditions about Diogenes of Sinope, the Cynic philosopher.

The Survival of Diogenes Traditions in Late Antiquity

The preservation of traditions about Diogenes in the school curriculum in Late Antiquity provides a suitable starting point for surveying comments about Diogenes and Cynicism in the writings of fourth-century Christians. Only then can we begin to understand what the figure of Diogenes meant to the architects of an emerging Christian intellectual culture. By the time of the early empire, Diogenes had become a cultural type, a πρόσωπον, a recognizable stock character. As such, he appears in works by a number of authors from the first and second centuries, including Dio Chrysostom, Epictetus, Plutarch, as well as in a collection of pseudepigraphical letters.[4] Each of these writers had access to a loosely organized body of traditions about Diogenes which circulated both in oral and in written forms.[5]

Familiarity with the figure of Diogenes did not fade away with the coming of Christianity. Sayings attributed to Diogenes and anecdotes about him were preserved (and even generated), particularly in the schools of grammar and rhetoric located in cities throughout the Mediterranean world.[6] Diogenes, as a cultural type, became an element in Christian culture, an example from the past to be referred to in discussion of a range of topics, a bit of cultural property whose meaning and significance were widely debated. Christians’ exploitation of Diogenes’ meaning was part of their synthesis of the cultural legacy of the pagan past.

Traditions about Diogenes were preserved in the rhetorical exercises, particular in chreia (χρεία), the sayings and anecdotes which formed the building blocks of rhetorical education and hence had direct bearing on the very art of speech making.[7] Drawing on literally thousands of sayings and anecdotes attributed or attributable to various ancient personages, teachers developed their students’ oratorical skills. Many chreiai were attributed to Socrates, Isocrates, and Menander. Perhaps the greatest number were attributed to Diogenes. One scholar estimated that, in all their variations and permutations, the chreiai attributed to Diogenes number more than a thousand.[8]

Chreiai attributed to Diogenes also appeared in other literary contexts. In the Lives of the Philosophers, Diogenes Laertius gathers a number of earlier collections of chreiai specifically concerned with Diogenes of Sinope in compiling his anecdotal “life” of the Cynic.[9] In this and other collections, there was little concern that the attributions should be accurate, only that they should be apt.[10] The requirement of apt attribution presupposes that the conception of a given character (πρόσωπον) was well developed and well understood. In order to attribute a saying to Diogenes, for instance, one first had to consider whether it was appropriate to his character. This character was based in large part on what had been attributed to Diogenes in other chreiai, the materials which formed a Diogenes tradition. Chreiai attributed to Diogenes shared a “family resemblance,” in that they portrayed Diogenes as a certain sort of character determined by a set of loosely related “biographical” details which were commonly “known” to have happened in Diogenes’ life, such as his exile from Sinope, his arrival in Athens, the fact that he carried a wallet and a staff and wore a white robe. Chief among the details were witty sayings, an ascetic way of life, and shameless acts.[11]

The wide dissemination of Diogenes traditions is exemplified in the work of the fifth-century pagan author John of Stobi, who compiled an anthology of poetry and prose from over 450 Greek authors.[12] As Photius relates, John presented “opinions, sayings, and maxims” as “precepts to discipline and improve his son.”[13] John’s anthology was copied frequently in the Byzantine world and has long served scholars because it preserves fragments of many texts now lost. Diogenes figures prominently in this collection; there are over sixty of his sayings, making him one of the most cited sources in the anthology.[14] Reading through the Diogenes chreiai in the anthology can give us a sense of what constituted the character of Diogenes in the fifth century. Here are some typical examples:

When someone asked how can one become master of himself, Diogenes said, “When those things which he reproves in others he reproves even more in himself.” (3.1.55)

Diogenes mocked those who lock up their storehouses with bolts, keys, and seals, but who open up all the doors and windows of their bodies, through their mouth, their genitals, their ears, and their eyes. (3.6.17.)

Diogenes said that virtue can reside neither in a wealthy city nor a wealthy house. (4.31.c.88)

As in Diogenes chreiai elsewhere, John of Stobi’s Diogenes challenges hypocrisy and praises the virtue of poverty. He embodies the problem of living a moral life for the urban elite.

Throughout the Byzantine era, Diogenes remained an important figure in rhetorical handbooks. Twelve Diogenes chreiai appear in John of Damascus’s anthology known as the Sacra Parallela, consisting mostly of sayings attributed to Christian authors compiled early in the eighth century.[15] Rhetors continued to employ the chreiai in their speeches, and their audiences continued to be familiar with Diogenes and the meaning that his character came to embody.[16]

School exercises, of course, were not the only factor in the preservation of traditions about Diogenes in Late Antiquity. The writings of the church fathers, as well as the Emperor Julian and the Neoplatonist philosopher Damascius, give evidence for the existence of practicing Cynics in Late Antiquity.[17] Some of the Cynics are known to us by name. Julian attacked a Cynic named Heraclius for misrepresenting the gods.[18] Patriarch Gregory of Nazianzus preached in praise of Maximus, a Christian priest from Alexandria who also identified himself as a Cynic and who arrived in Constantinople in 380.[19] Damascius’s Life of Isidorus gives a spare account of a Cynic and Neoplatonic philosopher named Sallustius who was born around 430 and seems to have survived into the early decades of the sixth century.[20] Moreover, sources from the period either address or refer to groups of nameless practitioners of Cynicism. Julian composed a speech scolding the Cynics of his day for failing to understand Diogenes and achieve his objectives.[21] Augustine was also aware of the continued existence of Cynics.[22] The Cynic way of life continued to have a powerful appeal into the fifth century.

Nevertheless, after the “army of the dog” had ceased to attract recruits, it was rhetorical education which guaranteed familiarity with Diogenes into the seventh century and beyond. Leontius, himself, had had such rhetorical training, as is evidenced not only by his allusions to Diogenes in the Life of Symeon, but also by its lengthy rhetorical introduction. Clearly Leontius had mastered the tools necessary to make a speech. What sort of Christian interpretation of Diogenes and Cynicism might he have received with his education? To consider this aspect of Leontius’s intellectual heritage, we must turn to the interpretations of Diogenes among Christians and pagans of the fourth century, since it was the reflections of such figures as Basil the Great, John Chrysostom, Gregory of Nazianzus, and even the Emperor Julian which framed the debate over the relevance of the Hellenistic curriculum for Christians.

Attitudes toward Diogenes

Already in the third century, Origen had cited the Cynics with favor to justify the Christian practice of preaching in public and the life of voluntary poverty.[23] The fourth century brought changes in the status of Christianity in aristocratic and hence in intellectual circles. As the relationship between Christianity and traditions of pagan learning was renegotiated, the figure of Diogenes was revalued. Basil of Caesarea, it seems, was quite fond of Diogenes the Cynic. In a casual note to a wealthy friend written around 358, Basil thanks his friend for gifts, joking that his beloved Poverty has been driven away. He muses that Poverty would object, since she had decided to live with Basil in the first place because he praised Zeno and Cleanthes and had donned the philosopher’s cloak. “As for Diogenes,” protests Poverty,

[Basil] has never ceased to admire him, who, endeavoring to be satisfied by the things derived from nature alone threw away even his drinking cup, after he learned from a boy how to bend over and drink from the hollow of his hands.[24]

As he appears here, Diogenes might be taken for just one of many elements of the literary culture which Late Roman gentlemen shared and to which they might make witty reference. Basil’s commitment to the traditions which transmitted this literary culture, articulated in his Letter to Young Men on How They Might Benefit from Pagan Literature, is evidence for a balance struck between Christianity and Greek paideia in Christian intellectual circles. Basil’s formulation of the balance between Christian values and pagan culture had crucial consequences for the whole of Christian intellectual history in the East. With Basil, Diogenes became firmly rooted in a Christian intellectual tradition. Basil’s Letter to Young Men had tremendous influence in Late Antiquity and in Byzantine times, shaping a Christian philosophy of education that accommodated prevailing Late Antique pagan curricula.[25]

Basil felt that the example of Diogenes which was presented in the educational curriculum was instructive and worthy of inclusion in the canon of information to be passed on to Christian students. In Basil’s letter on pagan literature, among references to Homer and Hesiod, Plato and Plutarch, are passages based on chreiai attributed to Diogenes of Sinope. Diogenes exemplified a form of behavior which Basil felt was desirable for Christian youths. Basil writes,

[T]o spend one’s time, beyond what is necessary, on the care of the hair or on dress, is, according to the saying of Diogenes, the mark of men who are either unfortunate or doing wrong.[26] Hence, to be a dandy and get the name of being one ought, I maintain, to be considered by persons so inclined just as disgraceful as to keep company with harlots or to seduce other men’s wives. For what difference should it make, at least to a man of sense, whether he is clothed in a costly robe or wears a cheap workman’s cloak, so long as what he has on gives adequate protection against the cold of winter and the heat of summer?[27]

And later,

I admire also the scorn of Diogenes for all human good without exception, who declared himself richer than the Great King [Alexander the Great] by reason of the fact that he needed less for living than the King.[28]

Thus, Diogenes’ simple comportment—rather than his shameless acts—received Basil’s praise.

Not only was Diogenes a moral exemplar, he was also an instrument of polemic. The pagan tradition, of course, was not static in this era, and the meaning of the figure of Diogenes was debated by pagans as well as Christians. There is no better evidence of the pagan concern to revalue the legacy of the Cynic tradition in this era than the writings of the Emperor Julian. Julian’s oration directed against “uneducated Cynics” was probably composed in Constantinople, late in the spring of 362.[29] In this speech Julian defended Diogenes from criticisms which had been directed against him by contemporary Cynics, especially that Diogenes was foolish when he ingested raw octopus. Julian defended this deed, as well as many of Diogenes’ acts of shamelessness, by arguing that Diogenes’ intent was to determine which activities humans engaged in on account of nature, and which they engaged in merely to conform to social convention (δόξα).[30] Julian presents Diogenes as a model against which to judge contemporary Cynics, and in fact all philosophers. For Julian, Diogenes is the ideal pagan philosophical type, and Diogenes’ shameless acts are an essential and even laudable aspect of his character. Although Julian states he is responding to Cynic allegations against Diogenes in this oration, criticism was also leveled at Diogenes by Christians, and Julian seems to have taken on the defense of a pagan philosophical type in order to present Diogenes as an alternative to Christian asceticism.

Shortly after he composed this oration against the “uneducated Cynics,” Julian spent time in residence at Antioch. When Julian’s remarks about Diogenes are read against the comments of John Chrysostom, a monk and later presbyter at Antioch, we can see that the value of Diogenes as a model for moral behavior was part of the larger debate between pagans and Christians in the second half of the fourth century over which community was the legitimate heir of Greco-Roman educational and philosophical traditions.

Although his writings have led one modern critic to suggest that he “retained little admiration” for the poets and philosophers he had read in the pagan curriculum, Chrysostom had been widely educated in classical authors and would refer to them in his own writings to make a point.[31] Certainly Chrysostom was not indifferent to all aspects of Greek philosophy, for while he was concerned to show that Greek philosophers compared badly with Christian thinkers, he was quick to cite the achievements of individual philosophers who had led lives which, at least in part, could be regarded as exemplary. Diogenes the Cynic received both Chrysostom’s criticism and his praise.

In his treatise Against the Enemies of the Monastic Life, John Chrysostom praises the ascetic virtues of Diogenes as well as Socrates and Plato. He writes,

Do you know how much money Alexander [the Great] would have given to Diogenes, if he wanted to accept it? But he did not want it. And Alexander tried hard and did everything so that he might some day come to Diogenes’s riches.[32]

He concludes, “That other philosopher, the one from Sinope, was richer by far than these and countless other such kings.”[33] Ironically, Chrysostom invokes Diogenes as an exemplar of the ascetic life in his defense of Christian monasticism. Chrysostom assumes that his audience is familiar with the story of Diogenes and Alexander, and that it was already inclined to think well of Diogenes.[34] Chrysostom argues that if Diogenes was respected by educated Christians for his way of life, despite the fact that he was a pagan, how much more should the Christian ascetic be worthy of respect.[35]

While Diogenes’ legendary impurity and shamelessness seem to have been overlooked by Basil, Chrysostom voiced his disapproval. In his Discourse on the Blessed Babylas, composed in Antioch around 378, Chrysostom compares the murdered bishop of Antioch to ancient philosophers. Of course, Babylas is superior to these men. Chrysostom accuses the pagan philosophers of “vain-glory, impudence, and puerility” and praises Babylas because “he did not shut himself up in a large wine cask, nor did he go round the market place clothed in rags.” The reference, of course, is to Diogenes.[36] Chrysostom chides Diogenes for his audacity in asking Alexander the Great to step out of his light. When Chrysostom’s imaginary interlocutor protests that “ ‘the man from Sinope was also temperate and lived abstinently, even refusing to contract a legitimate marriage,’ ” Chrysostom responds, “But add how and in what way! You will not add it, but prefer to deprive him of praise for temperance than tell the mode of his temperance, so foul and full of so much shame.”[37] The reference here is most likely to stories about Diogenes’ tendency to masturbate in public.[38] After condemning the approving attitudes of Aristotle, Chrysippus, Socrates, and Plato toward various sex acts, Chrysostom accuses Diogenes of being indifferent to cannibalism. Chrysostom presents Diogenes as licentious and morally irresponsible, hardly worthy of comparison with a Christian saint. What is most intriguing is that Chrysostom’s argument proceeds by countering a position which he assumes to be commonplace: that Diogenes’ way of life—his poverty, freedom, and temperance—was laudable.

The speech in praise of the martyr Babylas is directed “against Julian and against the pagans.” It is probable that Chrysostom was familiar with Julian’s oration against the “uneducated Cynics.” Julian argued that Diogenes had rejected common opinion in favor of a life according to the principles of nature, a standard interpretation of Diogenes’ behavior found already in the pseudepigraphic epistles.[39] But the Greek word doxa (δόξα), which Julian and the epistles use to mean “social convention” or “opinion,” also means “glory” or “honor,” a concept related to renown or repute.[40] For Chrysostom, glory was for God alone and was to be rejected by the saints. Chrysostom’s letter to a young widow argues that a number of ancient philosophers rejected wealth in pursuit of “glory from everyone [τῆς δόξης τῆς παρὰ τῶν πολλῶν],” that is, public recognition or common good opinion. It is precisely this virtue of the rejection of doxa which Chrysostom wishes to instill in the widow.[41] In arguing here that Diogenes sought doxa, Chrysostom contradicts the commonplace assertion found in Julian that he did not. For Chrysostom, the notion that Diogenes had been motivated by doxa was sufficient grounds to condemn him. In a homily on First Corinthians, Chrysostom says that the apostles did not seek glory,

Not like him of Sinope, who clothed in rags and living in a cask to no good end, astonished many, but profited none: whereas Paul did none of these things; (for neither had he an eye to ostentation;) but was both clothed in ordinary apparel with all decency, and lived in a house continually, and displayed all exactness in the practice of all other virtue; which the Cynic despised, living impurely and publicly disgracing himself, and dragged away by his mad passion for glory [δόξα]. For if any one ask the reason of his living in a cask, he will find no other but vain-glory alone.[42]

Here and elsewhere, when John Chrysostom compared Cynics and Christians, the Cynics were to be faulted for their failure to achieve the virtues of early Christians. Chrysostom is thus refuting a contemporary pagan evaluation of Diogenes and the meaning of the Cynic tradition in order to prove the superiority of Christianity. In fact, Chrysostom is specifically interested in discrediting this pagan exemplar who most seems to embody Christian ideals.

John Chrysostom’s rejection of Diogenes as unworthy of a Christian’s praise stands in great contrast to the opinions of his predecessor as patriarch of Constantinople, Gregory of Nazianzus. In a letter composed after he had been removed from the patriarchate and returned to his home town, Gregory addressed the civic administrators of Nazianzus, seeking to obtain a tax exemption for a local priest.

It seems to me that you would not spare Diogenes of Sinope’s wallet, if it were up to you; rather if [only] you could lay your hand on it also, and regard his cloak, staff, and his lack of all possessions on account of his philosophy as a profession, his habit of going from door to door, living life however it comes . . . [thus you would also tax this poor priest who serves the community.][43]

Diogenes here, as we have seen elsewhere, is a paradigm for a person living in voluntary poverty for the sake of others. Such a person is worthy of regard by civil officials and therefore by the town in general. Gregory’s reference to Diogenes has much in common with that in the personal letter of Basil’s quoted above. Diogenes was part of these gentlemen’s culture, and Gregory’s opinion of Diogenes was not unlike that of his friend and fellow Cappadocian.

This similarity is all the more remarkable given Gregory’s previous experiences with a flesh and blood Cynic. In 380 a certain Maximus arrived in Constantinople from Alexandria. Before his conversion to Christianity, Gregory explains, Maximus had practiced Cynicism. When he arrived in Constantinople he still had long hair and carried a staff.[44] It is clear from his garb as well as from Gregory’s description that, although Maximus had become a Christian, he remained in some sense a Cynic. The Nicene bishop of Constantinople, soon to be patriarch, Gregory of Nazianzus preached two panegyrics in his honor referring to him as a “philosopher.”[45] These two orations in honor of Maximus are, in fact, a defense and praise of philosophy, albeit a conditional one. These neglected speeches are exceptionally good evidence for a late-fourth-century synthesis of pagan learning and Christian culture, a synthesis which the Cappadocians played a leading role in creating. Gregory’s treatment of philosophy was far more positive than anything that would be found in John Chrysostom. Gregory refers to philosophers in general as “witnesses [μαρτύρες] to the truth.”[46] He continues, “Their splendid robes are angelic as is the radiance which they express in outward form in their bodies.”[47] The language here recalls that used of Christian monastics (and late Neoplatonist pagan philosophers). This speech was given when, of all philosophical types, a Cynic was on hand. Gregory was not just referring to the martyred Socrates. In Gregory’s eyes the aims of Maximus’s philosophy and his Christianity were compatible. For Gregory, this Cynic Christian was a “defender of the truth and a champion of the Trinity,”[48] worthy of comparison with the martyrs. Gregory refers to Maximus many times as a “dog,” punning on the commonly accepted etymology for the word “Cynic” (κυνικός, which can also mean “doglike”),[49] and says that he is a

dog [κύων], not by shamelessness, but by courage [παρρησία], nor by gluttony, but by living day by day, nor by barking [ὑλακή], but by guarding [φυλακή] the good and keeping watch over souls, and by wagging your tail at whatever belongs to the family of virtue and barking at whatever does not.[50]

The connection between Cynics and dogs is exploited most fully in praising the philosopher. Even in this high praise, however, we can see another vision of the Cynics, one characterized by accusations of shamelessness and gluttony. Maximus had, Gregory tells us, risen above the peculiar practices of his pagan predecessors—Antisthenes’ arrogance, Diogenes’ vegetarianism, and Crates’ fondness for group marriage—and was quite different from them in his prudence, continence, modesty, affability, sense of community, and love of humanity.[51]

Gregory’s affection for Maximus did not last long. A few months after Maximus arrived in Constantinople, he attempted to unseat the bishop and have himself installed in Gregory’s place. He bribed a priest who was a member of Gregory’s staff to help him and gained the support of a mob of sailors from the Alexandrian fleet, recently moored at Constantinople. His plan failed, thanks to loyal citizens who interrupted Maximus’s sham consecration ceremony. Gregory was understandably furious, and not long after, when he had resigned his post and retired to his native Cappadocia, he expressed his wrath in his autobiographical poem De vita sua, devoting a quarter of the work to this incident.[52] Explaining his error in praising Maximus earlier, Gregory writes, “It was a great thing for me when a dog trod in my courtyard and worshipped Christ instead of Herakles.”[53] But Gregory only condemned the man, not his philosophy. Concluding his narration of this episode he says, “Such is the philosophy of our modern dogs: barking dogs, and dogs in this alone. In what way are they like Diogenes or Antisthenes? What has Crates to do with you?”[54] Gregory echoes Julian in rejecting the Cynics of his own day because they did not live up to the examples of the great Cynics of the past.

In his later years, when he spent much of his time composing poetry, Gregory continued to hold that Christians could learn from virtuous nonbelievers, “like gathering roses from among the thorns.”[55] In this way, he continued to make reference to the example of Diogenes.

Who has not heard of the Sinopean dog? What else needs be said but that he was someone thus, simple and moderate in life, and giving these laws to himself, not observing laws from God, and not on account of any hope, so that he had one possession, his staff, an open-air house in the middle of the town, a round barrel, an escape from the force of the wind, which for him was better than dwellings laden with gold, and food nearby, not prepared with toil.[56]

For the retired patriarch, Diogenes’ life remained a romanticized ideal. Despite Gregory’s troubles with his Cynic contemporary, Diogenes continued to be proverbial for his virtuous poverty.[57] His obvious shortcoming was that he was not motivated by the love or laws of God.

Ambivalence Beyond the Fourth Century

Basil’s and Gregory’s enthusiasm should not be taken as representative of all educated Christians of the Later Roman Empire. In his monumental antipagan treatise The Cure of Pagan Maladies, Theodoret of Cyrrhus demonstrates his ambivalence toward the Cynic. Subtitled The Truth of the Gospels Proved from Greek Philosophy, the work dates from the second quarter of the fifth century.[58] Theodoret refers to Diogenes of Sinope six times in the course of the treatise.[59] His reproaches are numerous: Theodoret regarded Diogenes as “a slave to pleasure.” “He mingled with prostitutes in public, and he set a bad example for those who saw him.” Diogenes “lived lewdly, without restraint.”[60] Unlike the Christian “athletes of virtue,”[61] Diogenes, it seems, missed the mark, and was therefore an inappropriate model for the Christian seeking to live the moral life. Theodoret’s protests imply that for many Christians Diogenes remained a model of virtue.[62]

Christians did not share a unified stance toward Diogenes, nor was the position of any particular Christian toward Diogenes entirely consistent. Ultimately Diogenes’ shamelessness was the stumbling block for a number of Christian writers. In this regard it is worth citing the opinions of Augustine of Hippo, who argued in City of God that Diogenes behaved shamelessly “because he imagined that his school of philosophy would gain more publicity if its indecency were more startlingly impressed on the memory of mankind.”[63] Augustine, however, claimed that this practice was not continued when modesty prevailed over the mistaken notion that “men should make it their ambition to resemble dogs.” He continues,

Hence I am inclined to think that even Diogenes himself, and the others about whom this story is told, merely went through the motions of lying together before the eyes of men who had no means of knowing what was really going on under the philosopher’s cloak.[64]

Rather unimaginative indeed is Augustine’s remark: “I doubt whether the pleasure of that act could have been successfully achieved with spectators crowding round.” In what I believe is an otherwise unattested twist on the ancient chreiai, Augustine was willing not only to defend the Cynic’s shameless behavior, but to go so far as to deny it by claiming that Diogenes was only pretending to do something unseemly. We can only wonder whether this attempt to vindicate Diogenes was persuasive. For Augustine, the Cynic’s achievements were too important to allow them to be discredited by lewd stories.[65]

Interest in Cynicism did not wane in the period between these authors and Leontius. The late fifth and early sixth centuries witnessed a revival of interest in Cynicism among pagan Neoplatonists.[66] In his Life of Isidorus, Damascius praises the Neoplatonist and Cynic Sallustius, a native of Emesa (born c. 430), who practiced Cynicism in Alexandria and appears to have survived into the sixth century. Moreover, Simplicius, a student of Damascius, who chose voluntary exile in Persia after Justinian closed the schools in Athens in 529, refers to Diogenes quite favorably in his Commentary on the Enchiridion of Epictetus.[67]

In addition, one of the most cultivated authors of the first half of the seventh century was Theophylact Simocatta. Better known for his history of the reign of the Emperor Maurice, he also wrote Ethical Epistles, a collection of eighty-five fictitious letters purportedly written by and addressed to a variety of historical and mythical personages.[68] The work probably dates from the first decade of the seventh century. Theophylact attributes four letters in the collection to Diogenes.[69]

Into the seventh century Diogenes remained an element of literary culture,[70] a complex cultural type who stood forever outside the norm, chastising those who held too tenaciously the common values of the educated classes. Gentlemen continued to reflect upon him in the course of their studies and beyond. Although some Christians rejected him outright, others harnessed the power of his critique and incorporated it into Christian moral exhortation. He was invoked in treatise, homily, and private correspondence. The next chapter considers his invocation in hagiography, in Leontius’s Life of Symeon the Fool. What attitudes toward Diogenes might Leontius have inherited? The portrait is decidedly mixed. On the basis of the evidence examined here, we can make the general observation that Late Ancient Christians invoked Diogenes positively to support their arguments in favor of the life of poverty and self-control, and negatively to argue against surrendering to passion and lust. This Christian lack of consistency with regard to Diogenes should not be surprising. Christians presented a varied picture of Diogenes because they had received a varied picture. The variety of ways in which Christians employed the chreiai attributed to Diogenes reflected the diversity within the figure of Diogenes which the chreiai preserved. The figure of Diogenes was a blend of asceticism and shamelessness. And it was this composite which attracted Leontius.

Notes

1. Donald R. Dudley (A History of Cynicism from Diogenes to the Sixth Century A.D.[London: Methuen, 1937], p. 20) still found it possible to discuss Diogenes as a historical figure whose actions had specific content, although he realized that anecdotes and teachings attributed to Diogenes by Epictetus, Dio Chrysostom, and Julian were of little value in the attempt to reconstruct the origins of Cynicism.

2. Eating in public: Diogenes Laertius, Lives of the Philosophers (hereafter D. L.) 6.57, 58, 61. Farting: D. L. 6.48; cf. D. L. 6.94; Julian, Or. 6.202b; cf. Epictetus, Disc. 3.22.80. Urinating: D. L. 6.46. Masturbating: D. L. 6.46, 69; Epp. Diog. 35, 42, 44; Dio Chrys., Disc. 6.16–20; Athenaeus, Deip. 4.145ff. Defecating: Dio Chrys., Disc. 8.36; Julian, Or. 6.202b, c.

3. On the history of Cynicism in general see Dudley, History of Cynicism. Léonce Paquet, Les Cyniques grecs (Ottawa: Ëditions de l’Université d’Ottawa, 1975) collects anecdotes relating to each major Cynic. An overview of Cynic thought and ways of life can be found in Ferrand Sayre, Greek Cynicism and Sources of Cynicism (Baltimore: Furst, 1948); and Heinrich Niehues-Pröbsting, Der Kynismus des Diogenes und der Begriff des Zynismus (Munich: Funk, 1979). Studies of individual topics include Ragnar Hoïstad, Cynic Hero and Cynic King (Uppsala: Gleerup, 1948); Harold W. Attridge, First Century Cynicism in the Epistles of Heraclitus (Missoula, Mont.: Scholars, 1976); I. Nachov, “Der Mensch in der Philosophie der Kyniker,” in Der Mensch als Mass der Dinge, ed. R. Müller (Berlin: Akademie-Verlag, 1976), pp. 361–98; Abraham J. Malherbe, “Self-Definition among Epicureans and Cynics,” in Jewish and Christian Self-Definition in the Greco-Roman World, vol. 3, ed. B. F. Meyer and E. P. Sanders (Philadelphia: Fortress, 1983), pp. 46–59; Jean-Marie Meillard, “L’Anti-intellectuelisme de Diogène le Cynique,” RevThPh 115 (1983): 233–46; Marie-Odile Goulet-Cazé, L’Ascèse cynique: Un commentaire de Diogène Laërce VI:70–71 (Paris: Vrin, 1986); Margarethe Billerbeck, Epiktet, Vom Kynismus: Herausgegeben und Übersetzung mit einem Kommentar (Leiden: Brill, 1978); and Rudolf Asmus, “Der Kyniker Sallustius bei Damascius,” Neue Jarbücher für das klassisch altertum Geschichte und deutsche Literatur 25 (1910): 504–22. For students of the history of Christianity, the study of Cynicism has contributed to an understanding of the reception of pagan literary genres such as the diatribe and the chreia by the authors of various writings in the New Testament. The classic study is Rudolf Bultmann, Der Stil der paulinischen Predigt und die kynisch-stoische Diatribe (Göttingen: Vanderhoeck und Ruprecht, 1910). Abraham Malherbe’s writings on Paul and the Cynics are now collected in Paul and the Thessalonians (Philadelphia: Fortress, 1987), and in Paul and the Popular Philosophers (Minneapolis: Fortress, 1989). F. Gerald Downing, Cynics and Christian Origins (Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark, 1992), collects many of his earlier articles. See also J. S. Kloppenborg, The Formation of Q (Philadelphia: Fortress, 1987), pp. 306–25, and Burton Mack, The Myth of Innocence (Philadelphia: Fortress, 1988), pp. 67–69. For a consideration of post–New Testament Christian attitudes toward Cynicism, see my “Diogenes the Cynic among the Fourth-Century Fathers,” VC 47 (1993): 29–49; and my “The Bawdy and Society: The Shamelessness of Diogenes in Roman Imperial Culture,” in The Cynics: The Movement in Antiquity and Its Legacy for Europe, ed. R. Bracht Branham and Marie-Odile Goulet-Cazé, forthcoming.

4. We also find him earlier in the writings of Cicero and elsewhere. Dio Chrysostom, Epictetus, Plutarch, and Cicero are available in the Loeb Classical Library. The corpus of pseudepigraphic letters is available with translation in Abraham J. Malherbe, The Cynic Epistles: A Study Edition (Missoula, Mont.: Scholars, 1977).

5. Gunnar Rudberg, “Zur Diogenes Tradition” and “Zum Diogenes Typus,” Symbolae Osloenses 14 (1935): 22–43; 15 (1936): 1–18. Using methods parallel to those developed by Rudolf Bultmann, Rudberg tried to describe the development of the Cynic tradition through the history of these formal units. For a more specialized discussion of gnomic anthologies which include Diogenes traditions, see J. Barns, “A New Gnomologium,” Classical Quarterly, 44 (1950): 127–37; 45 (1951): 1–19.

6. M. Luz, “A Description of the Greek Cynic in the Jerusalem Talmud,” JSJ 20 (1989): 49–60, has recently shown that the rabbis were familiar with traditions about the Cynics.

7. Ronald F. Hock and Edward N. O’Neil, The Chreia in Ancient Rhetoric, vol. 1, The Progymnasmata (Atlanta: Scholars, 1986), contains all the chapters on the chreia found in ancient textbooks, with English translations. According to a textbook on rhetoric written by Theon of Alexandria in the second half of the first century, the chreia is “a concise statement or action which is attributed with aptness [εὐστοχία] to some specified character [πρόσωπον] or to something analogous to a character” (Hock and O’Neil, The Chreia, pp. 82–83, text and translation). See also Krueger, “Diogenes the Cynic,” pp. 31–32.

8. Henry A. Fischel, “Studies in Cynicism and the Ancient Near East: The Transformation of a Chria” [sic], in Religions in Antiquity: Essays in Memory of Erwin Ramsdell Goodenough, ed. J. Neusner (Leiden: Brill, 1968), p. 374. In Theon’s discussion of the chreia, seven of the twenty-nine chreiai which he uses as examples are attributed to Diogenes. Diogenes is also well represented in later textbooks. Hermogenes, writing in the second century, has one chreia attributed to Diogenes out of three examples; Aphthonius of Antioch (late fourth, early fifth century), who appears to be dependent on Hermogenes for his selection, has one Diogenes chreia of four; Nicholas of Myra, writing in the sixth century, uses one of eight. Although Aphthonius became the standard rhetorical textbook sometime after the first half of the sixth century, Theon continued to be read (cf. Hock and O’Neil, The Chreia, p. 212).

9. Diogenes Laertius cites a certain “Sale of Diogenes” by Menippus (6.29) and a book of the same title by Eubulus (6.31), as well as books of chreiai by Hecato (6.32) and Metrocles (6.33) as his sources. On Diogenes Laertius’s sources for Diogenes of Sinope see K. von Fritz, Quellenuntersuchung zu Leben und Philosophie des Diogenes von Sinope (Leipzig: Dietrich, 1926); Hoïstad, Cynic Hero, p. 116; Richard Hope, The Book of Diogenes Laertius (New York: Columbia University Press, 1930). See also Rudberg, “Zum Diogenes Tradition” and “Zum Diogenes Typus.”

10. Studies attempting to assess the authenticity of these and other sayings and deeds attributed to Diogenes are ultimately futile, since the whole point of the school exercises was to manipulate these statements and thus change them.

11. The full range of such details can be found in Diogenes Laertius’s life of Diogenes, Lives of the Philosophers 6.20–81.

12. The edition cited here is John of Stobi, Anthologium, 5 vols., 2nd. ed., ed. C. Wachsmuth and O. Hense (Berlin: Weidmann, 1958). Of continuing usefulness is John of Stobi, Florilegium, 4 vols., ed. Augustus Meineke (Leipzig: Taubner, 1855–57); this edition uses a different numbering system from Wachsmuth and Hense.

13. Photius, Bibl. cod. 167.

14. For an index of these citations, see Wachsmuth and Hense. Most of the Diogenes material has been translated into French by Léonce Paquet and appears interspersed throughout his own Diogenes anthology in Les Cyniques grecs, pp. 59–108.

15. During the eighth century John of Damascus, often regarded as the last writer of the Patristic period, compiled an anthology in much the same style as John of Stobi’s anthology, grouping quotations under various headings. John of Damascus, however, drew his material primarily from Christian authors, mostly theologians. Materials from “profane” and non-Christian sources make up a small part of the Sacred Parallels, but among these pieces of the pagan world are twelve sayings attributed to Diogenes. Selections from the “profane” authors are included in the fourth volume of Meineke’s edition of John of Stobi. See John of Damascus, Sacra Parallela, PG 95–96. Karl Holl (“Die Sacra Parallela des Johannes Damascenus,” Texte und Untersuchungen 16 [1897]: 1–392) argued convincingly for the authenticity of the work. Also worthy of mention are the few sayings of Diogenes in the so-called Florilegium Monacense once attributed to a seventh-century writer named Maximus—most likely not Maximus the Confessor—for which a date as late as the late ninth through early eleventh century has also been suggested. The text is included in Meineke’s edition of John of Stobi’s Anthology, 4:267–90. On the date see A. Ehrhard, “Zu den ‘Sacra Parallela’ des Johannes Damascenus und dem Florilegium des ‘Maximus,’ ” BZ 10 (1901): 394–415. On further discussion of this question and on Patristic florilegia in general see Marcel Richard, “Florilèges spirituels grecs,” DS.

16. I do not mean to suggest that the transmission of traditions about Diogenes in Late Antiquity was limited to his survival among educated elites. We must imagine that oral traditions contributed to the preservation and dissemination of anecdotes about Diogenes.

17. Although Dudley’s History of Cynicism (pp. 202–8) devotes only seven pages to the period from the third to the sixth centuries, the evidence suggests that practicing Cynics continued to be a feature of urban life until the decades immediately preceding the reign of Justinian.

18. Julian, Or. 7. For Julian, the speech against Heraclius was an occasion to praise the value of mythology—a mythology which had been rejected by the growing number of Christians around him. Julian advocates a purer Cynicism which could be part of a pagan front against the Christians. Cf. Johannes Geffcken, The Last Days of Greco-Roman Paganism, trans. Sabine MacCormack (Amsterdam: North Holland, 1978), p. 151.

19. On Gregory and Maximus, see below.

20. Damascius’s Life of Isidorus has been reconstructed from fragments appearing in Photius and in the Suda. Damascii vitae Isidori reliquiae, ed. Clemens Zintzen (Hildesheim: Olms, 1967).

21. Julian, Or. 6.

22. Augustine, Civ. Dei 14.20.

23. Origen, Contra Celsum 3.50.

24. Basil, Ep. 4. Variants of this chreia include Plutarch, Mor. 79e; D. L. 6.37; Ep. Diog. 6.

25. Cf. H. I. Marrou, A History of Education in Antiquity, trans. George Lamb (1956; rpt., Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1982), pp. 321–22, 340–42. While Marrou is right to observe that Basil is warning against the dangers inherent in reading pagan literature, he underestimates the degree to which Basil is presenting a defense of the extant canon. The letter was addressed to Basil’s nephews, and it is unclear whether Basil intended it for wide circulation. Numerous manuscripts survive from the late ninth century on, by which time it had become widely used as a school text. The existence of Syriac translations of the text, the first from the fifth century and the second from the seventh, suggests that Basil’s letter was widely read. On the history of the text and translations, see N. G. Wilson, Saint Basil on the Value of Greek Literature (London: Duckworth, 1975), pp. 72–73.

26. Cf. D. L. 6.54 and Stobaeus, 3.6.38.

27. Basil, Leg. lib. gent. 9.3, 4. Text and English translation, Letters, vol. 4, ed. and trans. Roy J. Deferrari and Martin R. P. McGuire (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1962), pp. 415–17.

28. Basil, Leg. lib. gent. 9.20; trans. Deferrari and McGuire, pp. 425–27. Dio Chrys. Or. 6.6 ff. is an expansion of the chreia which stands behind this statement. See also Plutarch, Mor. 499b and 604c.

29. Julian, Or. 6. The date is suggested by Julian’s reference to the summer solstice in the opening of the speech (181a). Cf. G. W. Bowersock, Julian the Apostate (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1978), p. 71.

30. On the terms δόξα and άδοξος in Cynicism see Malherbe, “Ps-Heraclitus, Ep. 4: The Divinization of the Wise Man,” JAC 21 (1978): 60.

31. P. R. Coleman-Norton, “St. Chrysostom and the Greek Philosophers,” Classical Philology 25 (1930): 305. On Diogenes and other Cynics, see pp. 307–9.

32. John Chrysostom, Adversus oppugnatores vitae monasticae 2.4, PG 47.337.

33. John Chrysostom, Ad. op. vit. monast. 2.5, PG 47.339.

34. Furthermore, Chrysostom, ever suspicious of pretension, praised Diogenes and Crates, as well as Socrates, for not having mastered the art of eloquence—an ironic point perhaps in light of Chrysostom’s rhetorical skill. John Chrysostom, Ad. op. vit. monast. 3.11, PG 47.367. Socrates, of course, was remembered as an opponent of the Sophists.

35. Chrysostom’s invocation of Diogenes in defense of monasticism needs to be considered in light of the considerable suspicion against asceticism among Christian elites. The decision to adopt the monastic life was seen as a radical break with the privileges and duties of the life of the upper classes throughout the Mediterranean world. Parents in particular resisted their children’s impulses to retire from the world. (Cf. the Life of Melania the Younger and the remarks of Elizabeth A. Clark in “Ascetic Renunciation and Feminine Advancement: A Paradox of Late Ancient Christianity,” Anglican Theological Review 63 [1981]: 240–57. The subject of parental resistance to the ascetic life deserves further study.)

36. John Chrysostom, De sanctum Babyla contra Julianum et contra Gentiles 8, PG 50.545; English trans. by Margaret A. Shatkin in Saint John Chrysostom, Apologist (Washington, D.C.: Catholic University Press, 1985), pp. 100–1. On the date of the text, see Shatkin’s introduction, pp. 15–16.

37. John Chrysostom, De s. Babyla 9, PG 50.545; trans. Shatkin, pp. 102–3.

38. Cf. D. L. 6.46, 69.

39. Julian, Or. 6.193d, 202c. Cf. Epp. Diog. 6, 42.

40. Cf. Lampe, s.v. This meaning can be found in Christian liturgical texts.

41. John Chrysostom, Ad viduam juniorem 6, PG 48.607; cf. NPNF (first series) IX, p. 126. On the question of how widespread familiarity with Diogenes was in Late Antiquity, we note that Chrysostom writes to this widow that she did not need to learn who the pagan philosophers he was referring to were from him, since “you know Epaminondas, Socrates, Aristeides, Diogenes, and Crates . . . better than I do.”

42. John Chrysostom, Homiliae in 1 Cor 35.4, PG 61.302; English trans. NPNF (first series) XII, p. 212.

43. Gregory of Nazianzus (hereafter Greg. Naz.), Ep. 98; Briefe, ed. Paul Gallay (Berlin: Akademie-Verlag, 1969), pp. 80–81.

44. Greg. Naz., De vita sua, ed. Christoph Junck (Heidelberg: Winter, 1974), ll. 767–68; English trans. Denis Molaise Meehan, Three Poems (Washington, D.C.: Catholic University Press, 1987), p. 99.

45. Greg. Naz., Orations 25, 26. The identification of the Maximus of De vita sua with the hero of Orations 25 and 26 is certain. On the Maximus affair see the excellent discussion by Justin Mossay in his edition, Discours (Paris: Cerf, 1978), pp. 120–41.

46. One thinks, of course, of Socrates. On Christian attitudes toward Socrates, see J. Geffcken, Sokrates und das alte Christentum (Heidelberg: C. Winter, 1908).

47. Greg. Naz., Or. 25.2, ed. Mossay, p. 158.

48. Greg. Naz., Or. 25.3.

49. On Cynics as dogs, see Ferrand Sayre, Greek Cynicism, pp. 4–5. Serious doubts concerning the etymology of the term “Cynic” and a discussion of the ancient (non-Christian) interpretations of the title can be found in Heinz Schulz-Falkenthal, “Kyniker—Zur inhaltlichen Deutung des Namens,” Wissenschaftliche Zeitschrift Martin-Luther Universität, Halle-Wittenberg (Gesellschaftsreihe) 26.2 (1977): 41–49. For dog Cynic in collections of Cynic chreiai, see D. L. 6.33, 40, 61, 77; Gnomologium Vaticanum 175, 194; Athenaeus, Deip. 5.216b; Florilegium Monacense 155 = Meinecke 4:278; Stobaeus, 4.55.11; Anth. Pal. 7.63–68.

50. Greg. Naz., Or. 25.2, ed. Mossay, pp. 158–60.

51. Greg. Naz., Or. 25.7.

52. Greg. Naz., De vita sua, ll. 750–1043.

53. Greg. Naz., De vita sua, ll. 974–75. Herakles was a hero for the Cynics. See Dio Chrys., Disc. 1.59–84; Malherbe, “Ps.-Heraclitus Ep. 4,” passim.

54. Greg. Naz., De vita sua, ll. 1030–33.

55. Greg. Naz., Poems 1.2.10, ll. 215–16, PG 37.696.

56. Greg. Naz., Poems 1.2.10, ll. 218–27.

57. For a general treatment of Gregory’s attitudes toward wealth and poverty, see Bernard Coulie, Les Richesses dans l’oeuvre de Saint Grégoire de Nazianze (Louvain: Institut Orientaliste, 1985).

58. Thdt., Graecarum affectionum curatio, 2 vols., ed. and French trans. Pierre Canivet (Paris: Cerf, 1958). Canivet dates the work from the early 420s; however, this may be too early. Cf. Canivet, Histoire d’une enterprise apologétique au vr siècle (Paris: Bloud et Gay, 1957), p. v. Canivet has shown that Theodoret is greatly dependent on Clement of Alexandria’s Stromata and Eusebius’s Preparatio Evangelica.

59. Thdt., Affect. 1.24, 50; 3.53; 6.20; 12.32, 48–49.

60. Thdt., Affect. 12.48. Theodoret (Affect. 12.49; cf. Clem., Strom. 4.19.121) remembers that Crates had surrendered to passion and “consummated his dog’s marriage [κυνογαμία] in public.” The Cynics were examples who prove the rule that “the road to virtue is rough, steep, and difficult” (Affect. 12.46).

61. Thdt., Affect. 12.32.

62. In fact, in his Discourse on Providence, written for an Antiochene audience sometime after 435, Theodoret lists Socrates, Diogenes, and Anaxarchus as examples of people who renounced wealth in favor of poverty. Thdt., Provid. 6, PG 83.649; French trans. Yvan Azéma, Discours sur la providence (Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 1954), p. 207.

63. Augustine, Civ. Dei 14.20; trans. John O’Meara, City of God (London: Penguin, 1984), pp. 581–82.

64. Trans. O’Meara, p. 582.

65. Concerning Cynics in his own time, Augustine writes, “Even now we see that there are still Cynic philosophers about. . . . [N]one of them dares to act like Diogenes. If any of them were to venture to do so they would be overwhelmed, if not with a hail of stones, at any rate with a shower of spittle from the disgusted public.” Trans. O’Meara, p. 582.

66. On this question, see Asmus, “Der Kyniker Sallustius.” Moreover, earlier Platonists were neither ignorant nor universally condemning of the Cynics. Cf. Eunapius, Lives of the Sophists, ed. and trans. W. C. Wright (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1952), pp. 346–49.

67. Simplicius, Commentary on the Enchiridion of Epictetus, in Theophrasti Charactares, Marci Antonii Commentarii Epicteti . . . et Enchiridion cum Commentario Simplicii, ed. F. Dübner (Paris: Firmin-Didot, 1872), pp. 40, 45, 49.

68. Theophylact Simocatta, Epistulae, ed. Joseph Zanetto (Leipzig: Teubner, 1985). A very brief description of the work appears in Michael and Mary Whitby, The History of Theophylact Simocatta (Oxford: Clarendon, 1986), p. xv.

69. Diogenes “wrote” epp. 19, 43, 46, 76, and is mentioned in ep. 60. He “writes” against wealth and effeminacy.

70. The continued relevance of Diogenes in later Byzantine intellectual culture is attested by Michael Psellus’s references to Diogenes in his praise of Symeon Metaphrastes written during the eleventh century. Michael Psellus, “Encomium on Symeon Metaphrastes,” Scripta minora, vol. 1, ed. Edward Kurtz (Milan: Società editrice “vita e pensiero,” 1936), p. 97.


Diogenes in Late Antiquity
 

Preferred Citation: Krueger, Derek. Symeon the Holy Fool: Leontius's Life and the Late Antique City. Berkeley:  University of California Press,  c1996 1996. http://ark.cdlib.org/ark:/13030/ft6k4007sx/